The
Debate That Changed the West: Grotius versus Althusius, by Ruben Alvarado
Alvarado begins by examining the work of Althusius,
specifically Politica Methodice Digesta
or “Politics Methodically Defined.” In this
work, Althusius does not focus on the ruler, instead focusing on the myriad
other actors and structures in society:
And the primary focus was on
restraint of power, not power itself.
As I have commented elsewhere, it seems to me that Althusius
attempted to mimic the governance structures of medieval Europe and Christendom
without the benefit of a universal Church that could stand against the king; a
tall order, no doubt. Alvarado puts it
this way:
As such, the Politica is a Calvinistic meditation on the constitution of
Christendom, a proposal for the way that constitution should be interpreted and
implemented.
As in medieval Christendom, Althusius looks for a balance of
the individual within a context of society as a whole – with God above it all;
in other words, an individual, but not completely autonomous in the way that
the individual has been defined since the Renaissance / Enlightenment.
I have examined Althusius’s work in some detail
before, so here I will summarize: Althusius builds from the family up, with
all subsequent relations made on a voluntary basis, to include the freedom to
secede from a previously agreed-upon union if one so desires.
These associations were meant to assure symbiosis: a shared life.
Althusius takes these associations as a given – no need to explore the
nature and beginnings of institutions such as family, extended family, and collegium (or guild). Men have in the past so associated and will
in the future do the same.
In Aristotelian fashion, they are
taken as given: “We discover no trace of a constructed state of nature in
Althusius. He is cognizant only of real positive human communities, symbioses,
with their own, characteristic laws.” (Alvarado citing H.J. van Eikema Hommes)
Up to this point, these associations are governed by private
laws. Beyond these and moving to an area
to be represented by fixed laws are cities, with separate administration for
secular and ecclesiastical purposes.
Above cities stand provinces, which also incorporate corporate
representation: the ecclesiastic, the nobles, and the commons – with the latter
further subdivided into city-dwellers and agrarians. Finally, there is the commonwealth,
representing the nation as a whole and holding sovereignty – with sovereignty held
by the people and not the ruler.
Subsidiarity is the principle in play: “That which can be
dealt with at the more local level should be addressed there, and not at the
more general level.”
The church has a role to play, in censure: acts that are not
“referred to the courts because they lack an accuser or denouncer.” Call these victimless crimes. Alvarado offers:
That there is a public interest in acting
against these activities is something that used to be understood by all, but
today is utterly problematic.
This censure involves two aspects, inquisition and reproof. Inquisition means investigation; reproof
means punishment – ranging from “fines, confinement in penitentiaries,
exclusion from the sacraments and excommunication.” Proportionality must be observed; on the
surface, it seems difficult to square the concept of proportionality with
“confinement in penitentiaries” when considering actions that lack an accuser
or denouncer.
It is for this reason (and it is a critical distinction) that
Althusius considers the idea of “rights” in the community – a city with fixed laws.
Of course, if one is free to choose his community, this does not seem
problematic to a libertarian eye. (I do
not speak here of unlimited choices in community, just multiple and reasonably
voluntary choices.)
In all cases, Alvarado introduces much more detail about the
nature of these institutions and their roles and functions; I will not go into
this here as these specifics are regarding his time and place. Instead, what of these “rights” in the community?
There is another topic of interest
which needs to be addressed in more detail, and that is the question regarding
Althusius’ use of the concepts of natural rights and the social contract.
Some see in Althusius a precursor of Rousseau and his social
contract – presumably due to this concept of rights in the community. Alvarado does not agree, offering a broad
discussion as to why he disagrees and also citing several scholars who concur
with his viewpoint. Instead, there is
the concept of citizenship, which is at play only at the level of the
city. Citizenship is as much a duty as
it is a right:
Citizenship is the right owed to
each member of the group, “the obligation and the power of communicating what
is useful and necessary as well as the right and power to participate in it.”
One has rights in citizenship to the extent that one also as
duties; these extend to those in his community or city. This has little to do with natural rights or
a social contract:
Indeed, we must realize that for
Althusius, “though the particular community may seem a matter of free choice,
living together is a natural process following its own eternal principles
without regard to the willful attempts of human beings, conceiving of themselves
as lawgivers, absolute and subject to no laws.”
“Living together” has its own “eternal principles.” Dwell on that for a while and consider what defending
these “eternal principles” might mean for a sustainable community. Members of the group do obligate themselves
to each other, but not in a manner that we would understand as a covenant or
contract:
This pact is “the fundamental
organizing decision of a living group whose common life transcends this
organizing act.” It is the efficient cause, the constituting power of the association,
but “belongs by nature to the living groups, just as much as life belongs to
the living organism.
The “common life transcends” any “organizing act”; it
belongs “to the living groups.” Dwell on
these also. This is nothing like social contract
theory as it is commonly understood, nor is it a matter of individual rights,
at least not in the way we understand “individual” today. This pact is described as “the efficient
cause.” Coming from Aristotle: the
efficient cause is that which brings the thing into being – what actualizes the
potentiality.
As best as I can grasp this “efficient cause” is the group and
it is its own entity, and it has rights.
The community is a thing with an end
or purpose.
Conclusion
While at least some libertarians would agree that a
community can voluntarily form under any set of rules and conditions as the
members (or “citizens”) see fit, this isn’t what Althusius is getting at. He is driving at the community itself as its own entity with rights in its
survival, with “survival” being described as something along the lines of
subsidiary governance and Calvinist tradition.
At the risk of being way off base, I see something of Hoppe
here. To be clear, I fully believe that
Hoppe would agree that a community is free to live under any rules that its
members choose. But Hoppe also suggests
that for a community to develop and maintain something approaching libertarian
governance, there are some rules and conditions that are more valuable than
others – even necessary.
I have not read Hoppe to ever write that the “community” has
“rights”; I am not going that far in introducing him here. Just that I see some similarities in that
both Althusius and Hoppe see the necessity of certain conditions that must be maintained
at the community level for a
community to survive in a healthy and peaceful manner.
What again is "community"? All those associations under the city or including the city?
ReplyDeleteIn many ways I agree with the Enlightenment idea of the individual. The individual must be recognized as having rights and agency. Without those individuals will be manipulated into serving the goals of some higher order without having recourse for protection and resolution of disagreements with that higher order.
I think where the Enlightenment really missed the boat was the idea that indviduals could truly own any kind of authority. If only an individual can have authority that is real anarchy. But no one in the Enlightenment and since then has been serious about bringing that about politically and societally.
Instead the State, supposedly on behalf of the individual, has removed the sources of societal obligation in order to produce personal freedom. However, the State does not and will not include the State itself as one of those sources of societal obligation. Therefore, the process has been described by bionicmosquito here, that there has been a hollowing out of society into 2 entities, State and individual. Now some are realizing that this lays individuals bare to the aggression/obligation of the State. Althusius realized this centuries ago, but wasn't able to implement his plan, or he didn't convince enough others to go along with his ideas.
But we now very much need to hear and follow Althusius' ideas on how to build back these intermediary structures into society, so that the individual will have protection and recourse against the State.
I think 2 things (among others) are necessary for that. One is to study Althusius' ideas and communicate them on. The other is protecting gun rights and even building some kind of militia system, made up of these "communities". Because history shows that encroachments on rights many time will not be stopped without violence. Also, it will be necessary to truly have subsidiarity and the ability to unite and then secede from previous agreements.