For longtime readers, this is a condensed version of the
several posts I have made on this subject.
I have also added a minor amount of new material.
Examples of decentralized society in history are often hidden. They are hidden because those in
decentralized societies never bothered to keep records. They are also hidden for the purposes of the
current state. I have previously written
about anarchy
in the Southeast Asian Highlands as one example. Here, I will present the time of the Middle
Ages as another.
This time offered a system of private law. A law not based on the edicts of the king, but
based on local tradition and culture. The
king was not above the law, but equally subject to it. For law to be law, it must be both old and
good. Each lord had a veto power over
the king and over each other law (I will use the term “lord” for those landed
free men. Even the serfs could not be denied
their right without adjudication. Land
was not held as a favor from the king; title was allodial. A man’s home truly was his castle.
Although the term has fallen out of use in the academic
community, for many this period is known as the Dark Ages – with all of the associated
stereotypes: barbarians, boorish behavior, and the uncivilized society that
came to Europe with the fall of the much more civilized Rome.
From Wikipedia:
The Dark Ages is a historical
period used for the first part of the Middle Ages. The term emphasizes the
cultural and economic deterioration that supposedly occurred in Europe
following the decline of the Roman Empire. The label employs traditional
light-versus-darkness imagery to contrast the "darkness" of the
period with earlier and later periods of "light".
How
did people live absent a strong central power (Rome)? In what manners was governance achieved? How did such a society evolve over the centuries
into the nation-states of Europe? From
whose perspective were these ages “dark”?
Hans-Hermann
Hoppe, in his essay entitled “On the Impossibility of
Limited Government and the Prospects for a Second American Revolution,” makes
reference to certain aspects of this time period in history:
Feudal lords and kings did not typically fulfill the
requirements of a state; they could only "tax" with the consent of
the taxed, and on his own land every free man was as much a sovereign (ultimate
decision maker) as the feudal king was on his.
Tax payments
were voluntary. On his land, each free
man was as sovereign as the king. This
doesn’t seem so “dark.”
Hoppe
quotes Robert Nisbet:
The subordination of king to law was one of the most
important of principles under feudalism.
The
king was below the law. This might be
one factor as to why the time period is kept “dark.”
Hoppe
references a book by Fritz Kern, “Kingship and Law in the Middle
Ages.” The book was originally written in German in
1914, and is a thorough and eye-opening examination of the relationship of king
and lord during this time period, as well as the relationship of both king and lord
to the law. I will rely upon, and will
quote extensively, from this book throughout this essay. Except as noted, all quoted items will be
from this book.
During
the early Middle Ages, there was no concept of a Divine Right of Kings, nor did
the earlier period hold to the idea of kingship by birthright. These ideas developed over the centuries and
only took shape in the late Middle Ages.
Contrary to these, in the early Middle Ages…
…an act of popular will was an essential element in the
foundation of government….
To
become king required consent of those doing the choosing. Additionally, the king did not hold absolute
power:
…even the rudiments of an absolutist doctrine had scarcely
appeared.
Both
the king and the people were subservient to the law – and not an arbitrary law,
but a law based on custom, “the laws of one’s fathers.”
All well-founded private rights were protected from
arbitrary change….
Germanic and ecclesiastical opinion were firmly agreed on
the principle, which met with no opposition until the age of Machiavelli, that
the State exists for the realization of the Law; the power of the State is the
means, the Law is the end-in-itself; the monarch is dependent on the Law, which
is superior to him, and upon which his own existence is based.
The
king and the people were not bound to each other, but each was bound to the
Law, giving all parties responsibility to see that the integrity of the Law is
maintained. A breech by one imposed an
obligation on the other to correct the breech.
The relationship of each party (king and lord) was to the Law, not to
the other party, and each had duty to protect it.
Contrast
this to the situation today: whereas today it is an illegal act for the people
to resist the government authority, during this period after the fall of Rome
the lords had a duty to resist the king who overstepped his authority. This is not to say that such challenges went
unopposed by the king –physical enforcement by the lords was occasionally
required – however, the act of resistance in and of itself was not considered
illegal. It was a duty respected by king
and people alike.
The
variety and conformity, through different times and in different places, of
church towers throughout Europe and European history bear witness to first the
centralizing control of Rome, and then the decentralization of the Germanic
period. Here I make reference to “A History of
Medieval Europe: From Constantine to Saint Louis (3rd Edition)”, by R.H.C. Davis
Davis
uses the architectural styling of various church towers built throughout Europe
to illustrate the decentralization of society that began with the decrease in
Roman influence. He begins with a review
of monumental architecture during the time of general Roman rule, preceding the
early Middle Ages:
Under Roman rule the general style of monumental
architecture had been recognizably uniform in all the provinces of the Empire,
from Britain to Africa and from Spain to Syria.
In the Dark Ages, something of that uniformity had been maintained…the
buildings of the Ostrogoths, Visigoths, Lombards, and Franks were built as
imitations (though sometimes poor imitations) of the Roman or Byzantine
style. But in the period from 900 to
1250 this uniformity ceased completely…in the Latin West there was a whole
medley of different styles.
Davis
then goes on to describe the differences: from Saxony, to the Rhineland, to
Lombardy, to Rome, and France:
They stand as monuments to the intense localism of the High
Middle Ages, when every man’s ‘country’ (patria) was not the kingdom,
duchy, or county in which he lived, but his own town or village. An echo of this sentiment may still be caught
by the French peasant who refers to his village as mon pays [my
country], but in the Middle Ages it was all pervading.
The
distinctions, region by region, extending to the area of law:
Even the law might change from village to village; a
thirteenth-century judge pointed out that in the various counties, cities,
boroughs, and townships of England he had always to ask what was the local
customary law and how it was employed before he could successfully try a case. The legal uniformity of the Roman Empire had
disappeared completely, and law, like the architectural style of the
church-towers, varied from parish to parish.
Davis
describes medieval civilization as “firmly rooted. It grew out of the earth, as it were.”
Before
going further into Kern’s work, it might be worthwhile to spend a few minutes
on the topic of serfdom. Kern spends
much time on the relationship between the lords and the king, what about those
on the lower rungs of society’s ladder?
The
term serfdom comes with a tremendously
negative connotation. However, when
considering this institution of social structure it might be good to keep in
mind:
Taxes levied by the state took the place of labour dues
levied by the lord….Serfdom is an institution that has always been commonplace
for human society; however, it has not always been of the same nature.
I
mention this not to justify, compare, or romanticize. However it might be beneficial to start with
a cleaner sheet of mental paper when considering historical serfdom. The serfs paid a tax in labor. Today we pay a tax in currency units usually
earned by our labor, and at rates often far higher than the rates experienced
by the serfs. At least the serfs had no
misplaced views about their lot in life.
Serfs who occupied a plot of land were required to work for
the Lord of the Manor who owned that land, and in return were entitled to
protection, justice and the right to exploit certain fields within the manor to
maintain their own subsistence. Serfs were often required not only to work on
the lord's fields, but also his mines, forests and roads. The manor formed the
basic unit of feudal society and the Lord of the Manor and his serfs were bound
legally, economically, and socially. Serfs formed the lowest social class of
feudal society.
Other
than the constraints on the serf regarding relocation, what about the above
paragraph is not applicable to today?
A
hint at the relationship between serf and lord is offered in the following 7th
century Anglo Saxon "Oath of Fealty":
"By the Lord before whom this sanctuary is holy, I will
to N. be true and faithful, and love all which he loves and shun all which he
shuns, according to the laws of God and the order of the world. Nor will I ever
with will or action, through word or deed, do anything which is unpleasing to
him, on condition that he will hold to me as I shall deserve it, and that he
will perform everything as it was in our agreement when I submitted myself to
him and chose his will."
The
serf pledged his loyalty to a lord who acted “according to the laws of God and
the order of the world.” His loyalty was
conditional: as long as the lord acted in accordance with “our agreement when I
submitted myself to him,” the serf was obliged to remain loyal to his
oath.
There
were remedies if the lord did not keep up his end of the bargain. A serf was afforded several social and legal
protections:
The landlord could not dispossess his serfs without legal
cause and was supposed to protect them from the depredations of robbers or
other lords, and he was expected to support them by charity in times of famine.
Many such rights were enforceable by the serf in the manorial court.
Presumably
being a serf was better than many other alternatives available at the time –
why would a serf insist on “legal cause” before being dispossessed by the lord? Why not simply rejoice at being set free?
Here
I do not refer to Frederic Bastiat’s classic
work, but the law
as understood in mediaeval times after and absent Rome, and before development
of anything even modestly resembling today’s nation-state.
Kern
contrasts this mediaeval law with what is referred to as law today:
For us law needs only one attribute in order to give it
validity; it must, directly or indirectly, be sanctioned by the State. But in the Middle Ages, different attributes
altogether were essential; mediaeval law must be “old” law and must be “good” law….If
law were not old and good law, it was not law at all, even though it were
formally enacted by the State.
Consider
how pathetic our society would seem to someone coming from this past time that
Kern describes. He comes from a place
that held that law was grounded in something more than the whims of the
king. He comes to a place where law is
defined as anything goes as long as the state says it does. And he sees a society beholden to this.
This
mediaeval time traveler looks back to his time, and considers that for law to
be law, it must be “old”:
Law was in fact custom.
Immemorial usage, testified to by the eldest and most credible people;
the leges patrum, sometime but not necessarily proven by external aids
to memory, such as charters, boundaries, law-books, or anything else that outlived
human beings: this was objective law.
And if any particular subjective right was in dispute, the fact that it
was in harmony with an ancient custom had much the same importance as would be
given today to the fact that it was derived from a valid law of the State.
Further,
he considers that the law to be law must be “good”:
Where we moderns have erected three separate alters, to Law,
to Politics, and to Conscience, and have sacrificed to each of them as
sovereign godheads, for the mediaeval mind the goddess of Justice is enthroned,
with only God and Faith above her, and no one beside her.
The
mediaeval mind did not separate justice from law – the law was to serve no
other purpose, no other objective, no other god.
The
monarch remained free to bestow privileges…
…so long as no one thereby suffers wrong. He can, for example, make grants from his own
possessions, so long as the community does not thereby suffer.
Consider
the simplicity and justice of this, and how foreign and corrupt today’s law would
appear to our time traveler.
The
law was always there, either discovered or waiting to be discovered. That bad practice at times overtook the law
did not change or replace the underlying “good” law. This did not require passing another, new
law. It only required the discovery of
the old law – discovery in its most simple and direct sense; something that
previously existed, waiting to be found.
“The old law is the true law, and the true law is the old law.” One cannot be separated from the other.
But
not today. Kern offers further views on
today’s law:
For us, the actually valid or positive law is not immoral
but amoral; its origin is not in conscience, God, nature, ideals, ideas, equity
or the like, but simply in the will of the State, and its sanction is the
coercive power of the State. On the
other hand, the State for us is something holier than for mediaeval people….
What
a miserable concept we live under.
Imagine our poor time traveler, the pity he feels for this miserable lot.
For us, the heirs of scholastic jurisprudence, law is only
secondary; the State is primary. To the
Middle Ages, law was an end in itself, because the term “law” stood at one and
the same time for moral sentiment, the spiritual basis of human society, for the
Good, and therefore for the axiomatic basis of the State. For the Middle Ages, therefore, the law is
primary, and the State only secondary….the State exists for the law and through
the law, not the law through the State.
By
this time, our time traveler must be rolling his eyes, wondering what
mysterious potion has overtaken this pathetic society. He is not naïve – he knows that the law was
not held perfectly in his time, that there were abuses and attempted abuses
that required a man to stand.
In
that regard, Kern offers an example of a lord standing for the law and in
opposition to the king. King Clovis
wished to retain a costly vase over and above his due, in order to donate it to
the church. All agreed to this except
one, who ended up enforcing his objection by smashing the vase. Certainly, the king was not pleased. As neither the king nor the majority had
authority to punish this act directly, the king found an indirect manner to
exact revenge; this had to wait one year, and was based on an equally
exaggerated instance where the king’s opponent stumbled in his duty and
obligation.
Where
was this old and good law to be found?
It will be found, in the first place, where all morality
resides – in Conscience. And, indeed,
since all law comprises all the rights of the community, it will be found in
the common conscience of the people….
…in the second place, the law will be found in old
tradition.
The
people themselves hold the law. They
know the good law because it is in their conscience – the keeper of their moral
sense. They know the old law, because it
is passed down to them. These two are
combined, always tested and testing.
Each individual had a duty to this.
The moral tone of the Middle Ages scorned considerations of
expediency, and always took right and wrong seriously, no matter how big or
small the question at issue.
The
idea of destroying a village to save it, or abrogating property rights to
preserve them, or stealing from one to help another in more need would be quite
foreign to the mediaeval mind – or to our poor time traveler, who would likely
have a reaction to this sad tale similar to this.
Kern
summarizes what has been gained and what has been lost via this transition from
customary law to statutory law.
For a simple person, in whom something of the mediaeval
spirit survives, it is a strange thing that all law should exist in books, and
not where God has planted it…. The positive written law brings with it learned
lawyers and scholars, cut off from the people.
Although in fact statute law is more accurate and certain, unlearned
persons become less and less sure what the law is.
How
often are we reminded: ignorance of the law is no excuse? This saying probably has roots in the concept
of law as understood in the Middle Ages – law based on conscious, law based on
a common understanding of justice.
Today, that saying is useless, given the thousands of miniscule yet
intrusive laws and regulations passed every year by various government agencies.
But it is in technical progress alone, not in progress in
ideals, that the modern concept of law is superior to the mediaeval.
Our
time traveler would certainly agree, as do I.
Imagine the liberty in such a world if every individual, or
even legislator, had such power. Imagine
no more: there was a time and place where this was quite true! And no, the outcome was not chaos, but a true
check on kingly abuse. Kern explores this further:
The relationship between monarch and subject in all Germanic
communities was expressed by the idea of mutual fealty, not by that of
unilateral obedience.
Especially
in the time of the early Middle Ages, there was no concept of the king as
sovereign. There was also no concept of each
individual as sovereign.
The king is below the law….if the monarch failed in these
duties [to the law] – and the decision of this question rested with the
conscience of every individual member of the community – then every subject,
every section of the people, and even the whole community was free to resist
him, to abandon him, and to seek out a new monarch.
As
time passed, the right of each individual to veto evolved into the right of the
community. But in no way did this change
the fact that the king was held to be below the law. Imagine if a single congressional
representative (for example Ron Paul) had the authority to stop any proposed
legislation! While not the authority of
the individual, still the idea that it takes complete unanimity for the state
to act is a powerful idea.
There
was no final arbiter other than the law.
Both king and community owed a duty to respect and defend the law:
To the early mediaeval mind, king and people together,
welded into a unity which theoretical analysis can scarcely divide, formed the
State. Sovereignty, if it existed at
all, resided in the law which ruled over both king and community. But any description of the law as sovereign is
useful only because it emphasizes the contrast with later political ideas;
otherwise it is better avoided. The
blunt “either-or” of later times – either the king is unlimited or the people
is sovereign – is an impossible dilemma from the standpoint of the early Middle
Ages.
A
significant ceremony was performed in 842, cementing the bonds between the
brothers Louis the German and Charles the Bald (sons of Louis the Pious) and
against their oldest brother, Lothar. Of
importance, this oath demonstrates the power of the lords and the power of the
oath. Each brother took a solemn oath in
front of the army of the other, and in the language of the other’s army –
Louis, giving his oath in Old French, and Charles giving his oath in Old High
German. The text of the oath is quite
revealing (from “A History of Medieval Europe: From Constantine to Saint Louis
(3rd Edition)”,
by R.H.C. Davis.):
For the love of God and for the Christian people and for our
common salvation, from this day forward, so long as God give me knowledge and
power, I will help this my brother [both with my aid and everything] as by
right one ought to help one’s brother, on condition that he does the same for
me, and I will not hold any court with Lothar, which, of my own will, might
cause [my brother] harm.
Then,
the people of both armies took an oath:
If Louis [or Charles] observes the oath which he has sworn
to his brother Charles [or Louis] and if Charles [or Louis], my lord on his
part does not keep it, if I cannot turn him away (from his wickedness), neither
I nor any of those whom I will have been able to turn away, will give him any
help against Louis [or Charles].
The lords
of Louis pledged to Charles that they will not support Louis if he breaks his
oath (an act of “wickedness”) to Charles (and the other way around, of course)! The kings had
no power absent their lords. And it was
the oath given by the lords that bound, not a decree by the king.
A Written Constitution:
Protecting the State from the People
Kern
examines the impact of a written constitution on the relationship of state,
people and law:
In modern usage we mean by the term “Constitution” that part
of the general legal order of a State which controls the powers of government
and the mutual relations between the government and the subjects.
Was
there such a thing as a “constitution” in the early Middle Ages?
The monarch was subject not to a specific constitutional
check, but to the law in general, which is all-powerful and almost boundless in
its lack of definition; he is limited by this law and bound to this law.
In mediaeval
law, the law was above both king and people.
Both were subordinate to it, and all (king and people) were bound to protect
it. Such an environment (without a
written constitution), while somewhat unstable for the people, was even more unstable
for the king. He was one man, equal to
the others under the law. He was controlled
by the law, not controller of it:
From the point of view of constitutional machinery, the
control exercised in this way by the law will presumably be very incomplete and
insecure – the very breadth of the mediaeval idea of law allows us to guess
this. But in theory there resulted a
complete control of the monarch, a subjection to law so thorough that political
considerations and reason of State were excluded and out of the question.
That
the monarch faced an equal insecurity and instability in the law as did the
people was the most remarkable check on any potential abuse. As opposed to modern, constitutionally defined
states where it evolves that it is only the people that have to fear the law,
in the mediaeval time all were equally subject to and therefore controlled by
the law.
The 1215 charter required King John of England to proclaim
certain liberties and accept that his will was not arbitrary, for example by
explicitly accepting that no "freeman" (in the sense of non-serf)
could be punished except through the law of the land, a right which is still in
existence today.
Magna Carta was the first document forced onto a King of
England by a group of his subjects, the feudal barons, in an attempt to limit
his powers by law and protect their privileges. It was preceded and directly
influenced by the Charter of Liberties in 1100, in which King Henry I had
specified particular areas wherein his powers would be limited.
Given
my understanding based on Kern’s scholarship, I don’t believe this document
represented a step forward for liberty, but a step back – at least when
compared to the early Middle Ages, when the king’s powers did not have to be
limited, as his powers under the law were no greater than those held by the lords.
The
constitutional form has protected the monarch from the people much more than it
has protected the people from the monarch – certainly when compared to earlier
mediaeval times. At the same time, the
constitutional form has provided virtually no protection of limiting the
actions of the monarch – even for those constitutions with some form of rights
embedded – for example, the U.S. Constitution with its Bill of Rights.
It
seems, instead of the pinnacle of governance and protection of liberty, the
constitutional form represents a significant step back from the liberties
afforded to even the lowliest members of early mediaeval society.
For
this reason the modern state feels free to create laws that run roughshod over
private rights. No list need be created
to demonstrate this reality of every modern state. This was not possible in the Germanic
tradition of the Middle Ages: “Nieman
ist so here, so daz reht zware,” or “No one is so much lord that he may coerce
the law.”
The
limitations thus placed on the mediaeval prince were, in theory, much greater
than limitations placed on any constitutionally-enabled monarch or president:
For the latter can establish new law in conjunction with the
other supreme constitutional organs, but the mediaeval monarch existed for the
purpose of applying and protecting the good old law in the strictest imaginable
sense.
No
one was “legislating” in the sense we understand that term today.
The mediaeval State, as a mere institution for the
preservation of the law, is not allowed to interfere for the benefit of the
community with private rights.
There
was no concept of the public good.
The State itself had no rights….It can, for example, raise
no taxes, for according to the mediaeval view, taxation is a sequestration of
property.
It
was only by preserving this good, old law that the king guaranteed security in
his position and dominion.
The
written constitution has placed the state above the law – the state
self-defines and self-interprets the constitution; the state has a monopoly on
the adjudication of its dictates. This
places the state in a position to decide what law is, and how law is applied.
The only hope one has to influence this is to turn a minority into a
majority. Such a concept was unknown to
the mediaeval mind – each individual held a form of veto. No majority was necessary, and minority
rights were fully protected – even for the minority of one.
What
changed, that brought man from an unwritten law, one that kept the king in
check, to a written law, captured in a constitution? I do not know with certainty, however I
present the following for thought: the change was grounded in the change from allodial land
title to fee simple title. This happened in England first, and preceded
the much-heralded written constitution, the Magna Carta, by 150 years.
This
change occurred as a result of William the Conqueror’s defeat of Harold
Godwinsson at the Battle of Hastings in 1066. As a result of this, William claimed that he
had won the whole country by right of conquest.
Every inch of land was to be his, and he would dispose of it as he
thought fit.
All
land was thereafter owned by the crown. Perhaps
in this can be found the seeds of the desire by the lords for the Magna Carta.
Conclusion
The
Dark Ages were not so dark. In this
time, law was custom. King and lord were
under the law and were bound to serve and defend the law. Each individual had veto power if he could
demonstrate the validity of his veto in the law, the old and good law. That the law was not written was not a
detriment to the people, but a check on the king. The king was as uncertain in the law as were
the lords.
The
early Middle Ages offer an example in history of political organization
different than what we today understand as government, or the state. One need not romanticize the period to take
away from it valuable examples of how life might function in a more
decentralized condition.
Thank you for this article. Highly enlightening and fascinating. At the same time, it is altogether depressing to see how far we have fallen in law, culture, morality, and genuine community. I am currently reading Nisbet's Quest For Community, and the medieval period is my favorite, for reasons well beyond stories of knights and damsels.
ReplyDeleteI do romanticize it, while recognizing how much I'd miss air conditioning and modern dentistry. With all their imperfections, however, the European people of the Middle Ages were much stronger in following Christ's additional commandment to "love one another, as I have loved you."
Today, the common good is hardly based on Christian love of neighbor. It is largely indifference toward one another, inertia, that keeps some semblance of peace. That, and fear of the state.
Sure, people still care for one another, though they hardly have rights. It is harder to care for others when the responsiblity has been transferred, and local communities have long been decaying. This must be partly why Facebook is so popular.
Aaah, the Good Old Days! And the Good Old Law.
ReplyDeleteVery instructive, bugman!
Thanx!!
Excellent, excellent article.
ReplyDeleteStudying Biblical law for the last decade or so, I've come to the same realization. It's not a set of arcane rules to keep the goyim in check, but a set a precepts that are the "old way", the "law of the fathers". Some, for sure, were based on safety for people before the advent of our modern technologies (i.e.: the prohibition of certain foods that are now routinely consumed with no ill effect).
Solomon shows us the application of what is the "old way" in 1 Kings ch.3 ( 35,36 ) - a ruler who was not above the law, but under it himself.
Look around in today's world. Surely (Proverbs 28:2) "For the transgression of a land many are the princes [bureaucrats?] thereof: but by a man of understanding and knowledge the state [ note: small "s" state ] shall be prolonged" applies to our modern, western, over-lawyered, society.
....and by-the-way ... the "legal memory of man" very nearly coincides with William the Conqueror’s defeat of Harold Godwinsson at the Battle of Hastings. Research _that_. ( AD:1189 )
ReplyDeleteIt's in the early (at least the earlier) law books ( see Bouvier's (1914) (and probably Black's (4th ed. 1957 & 1968)) ), and is a recognized fact of - even - modern law (see: http://www.in.gov/dor/reference/legal/rulings/pdfs/0120040364lof.pdf)
Excellent article. It forced me to reconsider my view of "The Dark Ages" and the effect it had and has on legal theory.
ReplyDeleteAll - I apologize for the delay in posting your comments. I thank you all for the feedback.
ReplyDeleteThank you, excellent article! I think you may be interested in two more works:
ReplyDelete"Those Terrible Middle Ages! Debunking the Myths,"by Regine Pernooud.
"Sacred Royalty: From the Pharaoh to the Most Christian King," by Jean Hani.
Wonderful books on medieval life and culture are Titus Burckhardt's "Chartres and the Birth of the Cathedral."
Also, his "Siena, City of the Virgin."
and "Moorish Culture in Spain."
Henry, thank you for the kind comment.
DeleteI will look into each of these books.
Mindblowing piece. I already accepted all of this, but this connects a LOT of dots. I will be forwarding this!
ReplyDeleteVery enjoyable piece. It is quite pleasant to read of the "Dark Ages"-a period I find fascinating-without the customary scorn.
ReplyDeleteIndeed, the era was de-centralized, and as such it is difficult to make accurate generalities. That said, there are a couple of areas I think some further clarification might be useful.
First, you mention William's conquest of England as a watershed, and indeed this is true, for in England, at least, it sowed the seeds of feudalism and the basis for a true "state." However, in many ways the Saxon Kings were already well on the way to developing a "state", albeit one that rested on traditional, or "customary" law.
Prior to William there was no such thing as a "serf" in England, and really no corollary social position. "Law" and "Justice" came from the bottom up, rather than the top down-people relied upon their families or other protective group(like trade brother-ships) to stand up for them and demand retribution if they were violated-or revenge.
The entire system hinged on the notion of "feud."(not to be confused with "feudalism" they are totally different concepts, the "feud" in feudalism means simply "in fee") If someone's family refused to pay restitution after a member injured someone from another family they risked the other group retaliating through feud. This was no small risk, since every family was like a small army. The offenders family would either pay, or turn the offender out without protection, which was essentially a death sentence.
The "lords" that there were were largely military leaders, and while they did collect taxes-they were collecting them from a heavily armed populace. There were slaves, and their was land-ownership, and a class system-but there was also social mobility.
By the time of King Alfred, this system had been slowly eroded by Kings with written laws. The earliest of these simply set written amounts for the restitution that already existed(in very specific terms.) Authority breeds more authority, and gradually laws against theft, and "the King's Peace" began to be enforced by the king, rather than by family feud.
That said, the Laws of King Alfred specifically permit the feud as a last resort to an injured party-though clearly he meant to curtail the practice.
Peter S. Wells, in a book I highly recommend-"Barbarians to Angels, The Dark Ages Reconsidered" offers archaeological evidence that not only were the "Dark Ages" less violent than the Roman era, or the later feudal period-despite the prospect of small-scale private war-but that there was significant innovation in farming practices and other technology.
To me, the most striking evidence Wells offers is simple height-during the "Dark Ages" the average height of Europeans shot up from the Roman era-and fell once again in the Medieval period. In the "Dark Ages" a man in England stood as tall as a man in England does today, and would have towered over his medieval counterpart by nearly a foot. They ate well.
Of course, this barely touches the surface of this complex and challenging era-I hope that it is helpful and supplements your essay.
Thank you for writing it.
A link to the Wells book(who is a mainstream academic):
http://www.amazon.com/Barbarians-Angels-Dark-Ages-Reconsidered/dp/0393335399/ref=la_B001HD08GA_1_1?ie=UTF8&qid=1361799720&sr=1-1
And Anglo-saxon laws written by Kings-the progression is fascinating:
http://www.fordham.edu/halsall/source/560-975dooms.asp
Thank you for these further details. This subject offers so much, and I personally have only scratched the surface. I will look into the sources you suggest.
DeleteInteresting article, but completely meaningless in any sort of relation to modern society.
ReplyDeleteThe "dark ages" were dark and there was nothing there of value to return to. Thankfully, anyone imagining it to be any different are in the extreme minority.
I'm afraid you've just demonstrated an invincible prejudice as well as ignorance of the subject matter, not to mention a prodigious lack of imagination.
DeleteGod, I hope anon is being facetious. Otherwise his ignorance is stunning.
DeleteLadies and gentlemen, the valedictorian of a public school! A comment perfectly regurgitated from a high school text book written by a cultural Marxist.
DeleteI've been pointing friends to this article all week. As a convinced AC this still connects a lot of dots for me. I only hope it proves thoughtful for those with whom I've shared it.
ReplyDeleteThank you.
DeleteI really liked the article. Pretty much all of it is (eye opening) news to me. However, I'd be cautious with the following argument:
ReplyDelete"Presumably being a serf was better than many other alternatives available at the time – why would a serf insist on “legal cause” before being dispossessed by the lord? Why not simply rejoice at being set free?"
Oh, well, today we see serfs going out in the streets protesting cuts in government spending and asking that the government take more money from them and make more decisions on their lives.
"Why not simply rejoice at being set free?"
Your point is fair; I didn't mean to suggest by my comment that this question was sufficient to demonstrate the not-so-completely-terrible life of the serf.
DeleteIn my further reading, however, it certainly seems to be the case that being a serf was a) not as horrendous as we are led to believe, and b) not the worst situations given the alternatives for those who lived life as such.
Much more color is provided in my more recent article, if you are interested:
http://bionicmosquito.blogspot.com/2013/04/liberal-society-hidden-in-dark-ages.html
Came to this article very late. Hope you don't mind a comment almost a year after the fact.
ReplyDeleteEvery reader should ask himself, "Why does the education establishment and the media spend so much time and money utterly trashing the Middle Ages as the Dark Ages as if it were the worst period in history?" I think the answer is pretty clear: because if we were allowed to understand the Middle Ages as they really were, we'd realize that we are less free, less civilized, less humane than they were. We need to keep up the myth of our own superiority. And the true mark of an inferior person is to trash someone else to build himself up. So, too, with societies.
What a fascinating article. Thank you.
ReplyDelete