There are a handful of thorny issues for libertarians – in some
case, significant issues on which there is significant disagreement. One such issue is that of abortion.
I will approach this issue utilizing the positions of two of
the staunchest libertarians of recent times – Murray Rothbard and Walter
Block. Both have written in favor of
abortion (although Block uses the term “evictionism”), and both have defended
their respective positions from what they consider to be a libertarian
viewpoint.
While I am not one that can hold a libertarian candle to
these two pillars (and also holding the two in quite high regard), my view on
this subject is quite the opposite – as mentioned, there are many libertarians
that would also hold this opposite view.
I conclude abortion is the initiation of the most grievous aggression:
murder. I hold to this view so strongly
that I am quite sure that no argument – libertarian or other – could sway
me. Forewarned is forearmed – while I
intend to make a libertarian case based on contract for my view, I approach
this subject with a strong bias; if this is a turn-off for you, perhaps you
should stop reading.
I will avoid momentarily the act of rape as cause of the
pregnancy, but will address this briefly at the end of this article.
I will start with Rothbard, and quote from his book “For a New Liberty: The Libertarian Manifesto.”
The book was first written in the early 1970s; if Rothbard had changed
his views since then (and before his passing), I do not know. However his views are consistent with other
libertarians on the one side of this divide.
Rothbard begins by recognizing the other side of the
argument:
For the essence of that case – not really
“Catholic” at all in a theological sense – is that abortion destroys a human
life and is therefore murder, and hence cannot be condoned….Murder is not an
expression of religious preference; no sect, in the name of “freedom of
religion” can or should get away with committing murder with the plea that its
religion so commands. The vital question
then becomes: Should abortion be considered as murder?
Rothbard then rightly suggests to avoid getting bogged down
in the “minutiae about when
human life begins….” From the first
moment of conception, what is conceived is either human or it isn’t. As we know the result nine months later, to
suggest anything other than human life resides in the mother is folly.
Rothbard then states his case:
…this is the crucial
consideration. If we are to treat the
fetus as having the same rights as humans, then let us ask: What human has the right to remain, unbidden, as an unwanted
parasite within some other human being’s body? …What the mother is doing in an
abortion is causing an unwanted entity within her body to be ejected from it;
If the fetus dies, this does not rebut the point that no being has a right to
live, unbidden, as a parasite within or upon some person’s body.
But the fetus was not “unbidden.” The mother took an action that might result
(no matter the precaution taken) in pregnancy.
I will suggest that the fetus does have a right to live in
the mother’s womb, a right in contract. When
an individual (man or woman) takes the action that might result in pregnancy,
he / she has made a commitment – call it a contract. This commitment is certainly valid for the
child once born; it is equally valid once the child is conceived.
Rothbard suggests just such an “out” clause:
The common retort that the mother
either originally wanted or at least was responsible for placing the fetus
within her body is, again, beside the point.
Even in the stronger case where the mother originally wanted the child,
the mother, as the property owner in her own body, has the right to change her
mind and eject it.
What Rothbard is suggesting is that the mother can break the
contract, even if the result is the death of the counter-party. It seems a rather one-sided “out” clause –
where the one breaking the contract suffers little if any consequence (in fact,
sees a net gain, else why break the contract?), while the ultimate consequence is
paid by the party that (presumably) was satisfied with the terms of the
original deal. It doesn’t seem like any clause
the fetus would have agreed to up front.
Most, if not all, contracts contain language that covers the
possibility of one party or the other wanting “out” of the agreement. Remedies include continuation of performance
for a specific time, return of certain forms of compensation, etc. Such contracts even include language for the
most significant breach (one resulting in the death of the counter-party, for
example), something like the following:
It is further understood and agreed
that any breach of this agreement by you will result in irreparable harm to the
counter-party, that money damages will not be a sufficient remedy for any such
breach of this agreement and that the counter-party will be entitled to
equitable relief, including injunction and specific performance for any such
breach or any threatened breach, and that you shall not oppose the granting of
such relief.
Certainly, if the mother changes her mind – as Rothbard
suggests – it will cause irreparable harm to the fetus. Money damages will not be sufficient. The counter-party (the fetus) is entitled to
equitable relief, including specific performance, and such relief shall not be
opposed.
Similar language is included in many contracts today, and
one would expect in this most one-sided contract between mother and fetus –
where the party breaking the contract suffers little while the counter-party
suffers death – it seems reasonable that the expectation would be not less than
what is standard in every-day commercial agreements.
I find Rothbard’s reliance on the mother’s ability to change
her mind lacking. She has entered into
an agreement, and one in which she holds all the cards. If she changes her mind, the fetus is
entitled to relief – and such relief would certainly be at least as significant
as that afforded in a commercial transaction.
Now on to Block. Here
he summarizes his concept of “evictionism”:
In a nutshell, the argument for
evictionism is as follows:
1. The unborn
fetus is trespassing into the womb of the woman.
2. The rights of
all fetuses are equal.
3. Therefore, the
only right choice would be evicting the fetus. Killing it would be wrong.
First, I find no trespass.
The unborn fetus was invited, one way or another, by an action of the
woman. Second, when the act of eviction
results in killing, Block’s attempt at splitting hairs is lost on me.
But let’s go on. He develops
the idea further here:
What is evictionism? It is the
theory that a pregnant woman has the right to evict from her body the unwanted
fetus, but not to murder it.
He recognizes that, with today’s medical technology, if the
eviction occurs prior to the sixth month or so, the infant will likely
die. However, he suggests, over time,
that improvements in technology will afford the evicted infant a chance at life
even if the eviction occurs earlier in the pregnancy.
He has written several articles on this subject, and
provides links in this piece. He also
provides links to some of the critiques of his view. I have not read them all. So my critique might be addressed – I don’t know;
if someone points out to me something specific on-point to my criticism, I will
read it and address it. Otherwise, I don’t
intend to read the almost two-dozen linked items.
What is my critique?
Block has used the language of landlord and tenant to describe his
concept – I will do the same.
The fetus, as tenant, has entered into a lease – not a tenancy
at will, but a fixed-term tenancy, with the term tied to a specific event:
birth. Such a lease was recognized in
common law:
At common law the duration did not
need to be certain, but could be conditioned upon the happening of some event,
(e.g., "until the crops are ready for harvest" or "until the war
is over").
The lease terms afford him certain expectations until birth as
long as the fetus keeps up his end of the bargain.
Can the landlord evict the tenant without cause? I have reviewed several typical real estate
lease contracts, and find nothing to suggest this is so. And without such a possibility, there is, of
course, no remedy proposed. I suspect if
the landlord wants the tenant out during the term of the lease, the landlord
must negotiate proper terms and compensation for this proposed breach. What would the fetus demand as
compensation? It doesn’t seem so
difficult to guess.
So, why would the mother evict the fetus? On what grounds? For what breach? There is no trespass; the fetus was invited. The fetus has kept up his end of the
agreement.
As with Rothbard, I find that Block falls short. In Block’s case, the landlord has no cause to
evict the tenant who has kept up his end of the bargain. The lease is for a certain term, and that
term being defined as a specific event.
Now, as to rape: the mother did not voluntarily take an
action that resulted in the pregnancy. The
pregnancy was the result of an aggression against the woman.
For this, I will revert to the non-aggression principle, as the
basis of libertarian philosophy:
The non-aggression principle
(NAP)—also called the non-aggression axiom, the zero aggression principle
(ZAP), the anti-coercion principle, or the non-initiation of force—is a moral
stance which asserts that aggression is inherently illegitimate.
Supporters of the NAP often appeal
to it in order to explain the immorality of theft, vandalism, assault, and
fraud. In contrast to pacifism, the non-aggression principle does not preclude
violence used in self-defense or defense of others
Aggression is allowed only in defense, and only against the
aggressor. The aggressor was the rapist. Whatever the fetus is, he is not the
aggressor.
Is the fetus trespassing?
I will suggest that the trespass occurred by the rapist. The fetus is merely the result of the
trespass. The remedy to the trespass
cannot include aggression against a third party – the fetus.
The fetus was not the aggressor; the fetus was not the trespasser. The mother therefore has no right to take
action against the fetus that might result in harm to the fetus.
I am certain many will conclude that my arguments here are
not very thorough, not as well developed as the arguments put forward by
libertarians who support abortion. This may
be so. As I warned up front, I am rather
biased on this issue. I find it to be
murder. I remain open to the possibility
that Rothbard changed his views over time, or that Block has directly addressed
the issue of landlord and tenant. If so,
and these are brought to my attention, I will certainly address these.
But I will remain firmly biased.
Well written entry with elucidation of your position and the reasoning that leads you to your position on the issue of abortion.
ReplyDeleteMy intellectual journey with respect to abortion ended in the same place as yours with virtually identical reasoning.
One cannot deny the greatness of Rothbard and Block, but even great men can get off course now and again in their reasoning. On the issue of abortion I do believe these two great men of the libertarian persuasion are in error.
Kirk A. Hayes
Pineville, LA
Kirk, thank you for the comments. I will reiterate the esteem in which I hold both Rothbard and Block, as you have also mentioned.
DeleteI only utilized the reasoning as I did in this post to directly counter the statements by Rothbard and Block - on their terms, if you will. I never really thought about it much in the way I outlined here prior to reading their positions, although in taking these intellectual baby steps, I feel ever more confident in my conclusions.
My journey and reasoning on abortion always began with the view that it is the taking of an innocent life. Whatever the cause of the pregnancy, the fetus was innocent of THAT action.
In the meantime, we rightly recognize that minor children are not responsible for many actions that would not be permissible for an adult. Can this be any less true for a fetus? Can the fetus be held responsible for a trespass? Given that the fetus had absolutely nothing to do with creating the circumstance of the trespass in the first place? It seems absurd.
We also rightly recognize that parents have many obligations toward their minor children that they do not have for others. If a parent is tired of his infant’s crying, can he throw the child out onto the woods (knowing the harm that will come to the child), claiming “trespass” as a defense? It is a laughable proposition.
For these reasons, I conclude no aggression can be permitted against the fetus.
Thank you, Kirk, and thank you Bionic Mosquito. Block's argument was so 'logical and reasonable' that I had a difficult time figuring out why it still didn't sit well with me.
ReplyDeleteThese points are a powerful antidote, and equally as 'logical and reasonable'.
Wow, you are so completely wrong. I suggest you don't touch the field of contract again, as you are mainly wrong on understanding those.
ReplyDeleteFrom your representation of Rothbard alone, it stands clearly that Rothbard is correct. It is so glaringly clear, I don't know why do you even argue this.
"[Y]ou are so completely wrong" is not very persuasive; neither is "Rothbard is correct."
DeletePerhaps you can shed some light as to your wisdom regarding contract.
Thank you for this much neeeded, well reasoned view. Nothing,-and I mean nothing!-can convince me that it is ever okay to abort a baby. Such an act of cruelty boggles my mind! Bluebird
ReplyDeleteBluebird, thank you for the kind feedback.
DeleteHat's off for tackling a difficult subject. thanks
ReplyDelete"But I will remain firmly biased." Doubly good as I agree with your point and admire your resistance to sophistry. I've seen Dr. Bock retract some of his unrelated (I think) statements recently. I think he may have a bit of devil's advocate in him; to see where logic might take one. I wouldn't care to debate him, pro or con.
Thank you.
Delete