NB: All previous chapters can be found here.
From an earlier
chapter:
Many libertarians claim natural law
as the basis for libertarianism, yet do not embrace the entirety of Natural Law
– they do not ascribe to the fullness of man’s purpose, but only ascribe to
purposes which are in conformance with non-aggression. In other words, the philosophy drives the
purposes and not the other way around.
This journey finally has come to this point – where natural law
meets the non-aggression principle. This
will be examined through the work of the libertarian that did the most thorough
work in basing libertarian theory on a foundation of Natural Law, Murray
Rothbard: Introduction
to Natural Law.
The aspect of Rothbard’s view on natural law that I will
address in this chapter is the idea that the discovery and maintenance of an
ethical value system based on natural law can be based on man’s pure reason; that
the judged can also be the judge. In the
next chapter, I will review Rothbard’s comments on the applicability of natural
law to political philosophy and morality.
Rothbard begins by describing the challenge for the “believer
in a rationally established natural law”: on the one hand, he is confronted
with those who offer that natural law can only come through faith and
revelation; on the other hand, he is confronted by philosophical “scientists”
who gleefully agree, thereby dismissing the entire concept.
He offers that those such as “St. Thomas and the later
Scholastics, as well as the devout Protestant jurist Hugo Grotius” have
demonstrated natural law via “the independence of philosophy from theology.” Setting aside what seems to me to be the case
that philosophy and theology are inherently intertwined – even for those who
disclaim theology, despite their protestations – it is a path that C.S. Lewis
also walked…to a point, as it can only be walked to a point.
I cannot escape the reality that this natural law ethic
reached its fully developed form among scholars who inherently were religious –
Christian. Given that philosophy
and theology are inherently intertwined, it is difficult to imagine that
scholars such as Thomas, the later scholastics, and Grotius, could so
effectively compartmentalize their thought.
No one starts such a journey with a blank
slate.
It also is telling that even though versions of the Golden
Rule are to be found in many cultures and traditions, no other culture or
tradition so developed natural law. It
is difficult to avoid the “Christian” behind natural law – at least natural law
that stood behind the freedoms enjoyed in the West.
Of course, we found the beginnings of natural law in Plato
and Aristotle: The Form of the Good, the Good embodied in the being, and every
being having a purpose or an end. If one
walks this path, one can discover natural law without necessarily incorporating
“theology,” albeit questions remained unanswered regarding who, or what,
created Plato’s Form, and in who, or what, do we find Aristotle’s embodied Form. Christianity answers both of these questions
– the first in God, the second in His Son.
Rothbard offers that this idea of natural law independent of
religion was implicit in Thomas’s work, and not explicitly stated. He offers direct statements from later
Scholastics, Hugo Grotius, and other scholars to this same effect.
Thus, let there be no mistake: in
the Thomistic tradition, natural law is ethical as well as physical law; and
the instrument by which man apprehends such law is his reason — not faith, or
intuition, or grace, revelation, or anything else.
Yet Jesus
was identified as “reason,” the logos:
Logos, (Greek: “word,”
“reason,” or “plan”) plural logoi, in Greek philosophy and theology, the divine
reason implicit in the cosmos, ordering it and giving it form and meaning.
In the beginning was the logos. I don’t believe this would have been lost to
Thomas.
Returning to Rothbard, citing John Wild:
Realistic [natural law] ethics is
now often dismissed as theological and authoritarian in character. But this is
a misunderstanding. Its ablest representatives, from Plato and Aristotle to
Grotius, have defended it on the basis of empirical evidence alone without any
appeal to supernatural authority.
Rothbard sees in Thomas that reason has the premier place in
moral conduct, and that it is reason that distinguishes man from the other
animals. Citing Father Copleston, reason
“enables him to act deliberately in view of the consciously apprehended end and
raises him above the level of purely instinctive behavior.”
This is not consistent with my previous
reading, for example, from Atkinson:
Aquinas…believed that God was
leading human beings to a rational, moral life, while Aristotle believed that
being moral was naturally inherent in human beings.
And also DeMarco:
The difference between the ethics
of Aristotle and Aquinas has to do with how virtue comes about. … Perhaps
Aristotle overestimated our capacity to be reasonable and under-estimated the
importance of love. Whereas Aristotle links virtue to reason, Aquinas links it
more properly to love.
As we examine this connection of libertarianism and liberty with
natural law, the issue of “the consciously apprehended end” must be kept in
mind, as must the point of rising above “the level of purely instinctive
behavior,” as Lewis demonstrated in the previous chapter. If we are to base liberty on natural law,
picking and choosing among ends that suit our instinct (or via some other
means) will destroy the entire foundation.
Pure reason, of course, can come to many conclusions. “Right reason” is offered as “reason
directing man's acts to the attainment of the objective good for man.” Moral conduct, if it is to be considered
rational, must be in accord with right reason: “reason apprehending the
objective good for man and dictating the means to its attainment.” For this, the phrase “practical reason” has been
used by others, and I have reflected this in previous chapters.
Reason, therefore, is not to be considered a slave to the
passions or to pure instinct. It is
intended to move man toward the objective good.
For the Thomist or natural-law theorist,
the general law of morality for man is a special case of the system of natural
law governing all entities of the world, each with its own nature and its own
ends.
But there is a vital difference in human beings – different
than for every other entity in creation:
And here we come to a vital
difference between inanimate or even non-human living creatures, and man
himself; for the former are compelled to proceed in accordance with the ends
dictated by their natures, whereas man, "the rational animal,"
possesses reason to discover such ends and the free will to choose.
It is right that Rothbard uses the term “discover” when it
comes to human ends. These ends
exist, inherent in humans – not for humans to decide, but to discover. Rothbard also offers that there is an objective
good; therefore this, also, must be discovered – not decided or
chosen. In other words, we have free
will to act in accord with these good ends or not, but we do not have free will
in deciding these good ends.
If there is an objective good, then yes – it is discoverable
by reason, but it cannot be true that natural law is a system that leaves each
human being free to choose his ends by using his own reason. If something is an objective good, can my
choosing make it otherwise or put something else in its place?
Rothbard notes that “science” scoffs at the idea of nature
when it comes to man. But he asks:
…if apples and stones and roses
each have their specific natures, is man the only entity, the only being, that
cannot have one? And if man does have a nature, why cannot it too be open to
rational observation and reflection?
And if man has a nature (as do apples, stones and roses),
does he not also have an end (as these also do) – one inherent, discoverable by
reason but not open to individual choice?
One common, flip criticism by
opponents of natural law is: who is to establish the alleged truths
about man? The answer is not who but what: man's reason. Man's
reason is objective, i.e., it can be employed by all men to yield truths
about the world. To ask what is man's nature is to invite the answer. Go
thou and study and find out!
And here is where Lewis and Rothbard will butt heads; as Lewis
offered:
…the judge cannot be one of the
parties judged; or, if he is, the decision is worthless and there is no ground
for placing the preservation of the species above self-preservation or sexual
appetite.
Returning to Rothbard:
The natural law ethic decrees that
for all living things, "goodness" is the fulfillment of what is best
for that type of creature; "goodness" is therefore relative to the
nature of the creature concerned.
When we consider ends for all other beings, we do not
individualize these: one lion has the same ends as every other lion; one rock
the same ends as every other rock. Why
would this be different for humans?
The natural law, then, elucidates
what is best for man — what ends man should pursue that are most harmonious
with, and best tend to fulfill, his nature. In a significant sense, then,
natural law provides man with a "science of happiness," with the
paths which will lead to his real happiness.
We will come to the idea of “happiness” shortly. First, an important point: Rothbard makes
clear that on this topic, value is not subjective:
Value in the sense of valuation or
utility is purely subjective, and decided by each individual. This procedure is
perfectly proper for the formal science of praxeology, or economic theory, but
not necessarily elsewhere. For in natural-law ethics, ends are demonstrated to
be good or bad for man in varying degrees; value here is objective —
determined by the natural law of man's being, and here "happiness"
for man is considered in the commonsensical, contentual sense.
“Contentual” is defined as relating to content, different
than contextual. It isn’t
completely clear to me how to understand this in the context of Rothbard’s
statement. I do, however, understand the
word preceding it: commonsensical. And
in this case, “happiness” cannot be properly understood in a way that would be
commonsensical today.
Recall from an
earlier chapter on Aquinas: happiness in the context of natural law comes
from the Latin word beatitudo.
This translates:
Beatitudo: (happiness or
blessedness). The happiness that comes from seeing the good in others and doing
the good for others. It is, in essence, other-regarding action.
It is a definition of happiness far different than what is
understood today; it is the definition important to understand Thomistic
Natural Law and the ends for which humans are to aim. Call it the Golden Rule, for simplicity. For liberty based on natural law, this seems
a significant point.
Rothbard offers a strong defense for the objective value
that underlies natural law. He weakens
his defense by offering that the judged can also judge. Rothbard offers Leonard Carmichael, who
indicates how “an objective, absolute ethic can be established for man on
scientific methods, based upon biological and psychological inquiry” as these
values have emerged over thousands of years.
From Carmichael:
Is there any reason to suggest that
these values, once identified and tested, may not be thought of as essentially
fixed and unchanging? For example, the wanton murder of one adult by another
for the purely personal amusement of the person committing the murder, once it
is recognized as a general wrong, is likely always to be so recognized.
Is it really so that as man has come to understand certain
ethical values that these have remained accepted thereafter? Thereafter, man is on a never-ending path
toward ever-improving ethical behavior? This,
I am afraid, is categorically not true.
FJP Veale has demonstrated
just the opposite in his book Advance
to Barbarism. There was a time, and
most certainly in the West, when war was a matter only of the combatants and
not the population at large. By the time
of the Civil War in the United States and World War One in Europe, this had
completely changed. Wanton murder went
from unacceptable to acceptable – in imagery, best exemplified at Hiroshima and
Nagasaki, but in reality offered thousands of times over the last one hundred
years and more. We accept this as normal
today, moral and ethical.
Abortion is another
example. While the legal situation
has been somewhat fluid and changing, it has significantly changed toward
approving of the murder of the unborn child and at an ever-increasing term. In other words, even though abortions were
known throughout history, the legal situation has not moved toward defending
against “wanton murder,” but toward legalizing “wanton murder.” Over 50 million per year, worldwide. This is also considered moral and ethical; it
is, in fact, immoral to consider challenging the mother’s “right to choose” to
wantonly murder her child.
Philosophically, this statement from Carmichael suggests
that man provides the north star; history has demonstrated that without an
independent north star, man’s ethical compass toward objective value is
useless.
From his Gifford Lectures,
N.T. Wright offers: “To be an image-bearer is more than just behavior;
otherwise we put the knowledge of good and evil before the knowledge of God.”
Developing and maintaining a society bound by natural law
will only go so far without also recognizing the embodied Form of the Good; it
will only go so far as long as the judged are also to be judges.
Conclusion
There must be something unmovable, foundational, and
objective at the base of natural law for natural law to play its role in
liberty. Something beyond and outside of
man’s authority and man’s reason. As Lewis
offered:
It is no use trying to ‘see
through’ first principles. If you see
through everything, then everything is transparent. But a wholly transparent world is an
invisible world. To ‘see through’ all
things is the same as not to see.
There must be something that man cannot see through, hence
something beyond man’s ability to modify, change, or re-define; something
beyond man’s pure reason. If not, we are
left with a battle of competing “reason,” and, for most of us, this means our
reason will lose.
Epilogue
Returning to Rothbard:
Another common charge is that
natural-law theorists differ among themselves, and that therefore all
natural-law theories must be discarded.
Hence the value of a judge who is not at the same time to be
judged.
Furthermore, difference of opinion
is no excuse for discarding all sides to a dispute; the responsible person is
the one who uses his reason to examine the various contentions and make up his
own mind.
But if each of us are free to make up our own minds –
especially regarding ends – how will we come to a natural law that is useful
toward liberty and peace? How will
justice be determined? Who will
arbitrate our “differences of opinion”? On
what basis?
No man is omniscient or infallible
— a law, by the way, of man's nature.
It is fortunate, then, that we have been given the omniscient
and infallible embodied Form of the Good.
Of course, I have no complaint regarding those who come to this natural
law without the same Christian belief. I
just don’t believe that a society can sustain this natural law without the
foundation from which it was formed.
This comment has been removed by the author.
ReplyDeleteWasn't Paul talking about the law of Moses, and didn't he say that the commandment that was supposed to bring life instead brought death? Paul's words are confusing and difficult to understand
DeleteJames is a much better example, he calls it the perfect law of freedom.
This comment has been removed by the author.
Delete"Liberty can not exist without Law, ironically enough. Make sense?"
DeleteYes, to me certainly. I do not know how liberty is maintained if man acts against natural law - the law with "beatitudo" as its aim.
What being can long act against its nature and remain at liberty? Only human beings seem to believe this.