Monday, June 3, 2019

An Examination of Althusius




Alvarado begins by examining the work of Althusius, specifically Politica Methodice Digesta or “Politics Methodically Defined.”  In this work, Althusius does not focus on the ruler, instead focusing on the myriad other actors and structures in society:

And the primary focus was on restraint of power, not power itself.

As I have commented elsewhere, it seems to me that Althusius attempted to mimic the governance structures of medieval Europe and Christendom without the benefit of a universal Church that could stand against the king; a tall order, no doubt.  Alvarado puts it this way:

As such, the Politica is a Calvinistic meditation on the constitution of Christendom, a proposal for the way that constitution should be interpreted and implemented.

As in medieval Christendom, Althusius looks for a balance of the individual within a context of society as a whole – with God above it all; in other words, an individual, but not completely autonomous in the way that the individual has been defined since the Renaissance / Enlightenment. 

I have examined Althusius’s work in some detail before, so here I will summarize: Althusius builds from the family up, with all subsequent relations made on a voluntary basis, to include the freedom to secede from a previously agreed-upon union if one so desires.

These associations were meant to assure symbiosis: a shared life.  Althusius takes these associations as a given – no need to explore the nature and beginnings of institutions such as family, extended family, and collegium (or guild).  Men have in the past so associated and will in the future do the same.

In Aristotelian fashion, they are taken as given: “We discover no trace of a constructed state of nature in Althusius. He is cognizant only of real positive human communities, symbioses, with their own, characteristic laws.” (Alvarado citing H.J. van Eikema Hommes)

Up to this point, these associations are governed by private laws.  Beyond these and moving to an area to be represented by fixed laws are cities, with separate administration for secular and ecclesiastical purposes.  Above cities stand provinces, which also incorporate corporate representation: the ecclesiastic, the nobles, and the commons – with the latter further subdivided into city-dwellers and agrarians.  Finally, there is the commonwealth, representing the nation as a whole and holding sovereignty – with sovereignty held by the people and not the ruler.

Subsidiarity is the principle in play: “That which can be dealt with at the more local level should be addressed there, and not at the more general level.” 

The church has a role to play, in censure: acts that are not “referred to the courts because they lack an accuser or denouncer.”  Call these victimless crimes.  Alvarado offers:

That there is a public interest in acting against these activities is something that used to be understood by all, but today is utterly problematic.

This censure involves two aspects, inquisition and reproof.  Inquisition means investigation; reproof means punishment – ranging from “fines, confinement in penitentiaries, exclusion from the sacraments and excommunication.”  Proportionality must be observed; on the surface, it seems difficult to square the concept of proportionality with “confinement in penitentiaries” when considering actions that lack an accuser or denouncer. 

It is for this reason (and it is a critical distinction) that Althusius considers the idea of “rights” in the community – a city with fixed laws.  Of course, if one is free to choose his community, this does not seem problematic to a libertarian eye.  (I do not speak here of unlimited choices in community, just multiple and reasonably voluntary choices.) 

In all cases, Alvarado introduces much more detail about the nature of these institutions and their roles and functions; I will not go into this here as these specifics are regarding his time and place.  Instead, what of these “rights” in the community?

There is another topic of interest which needs to be addressed in more detail, and that is the question regarding Althusius’ use of the concepts of natural rights and the social contract.

Some see in Althusius a precursor of Rousseau and his social contract – presumably due to this concept of rights in the community.  Alvarado does not agree, offering a broad discussion as to why he disagrees and also citing several scholars who concur with his viewpoint.  Instead, there is the concept of citizenship, which is at play only at the level of the city.  Citizenship is as much a duty as it is a right:

Citizenship is the right owed to each member of the group, “the obligation and the power of communicating what is useful and necessary as well as the right and power to participate in it.”

One has rights in citizenship to the extent that one also as duties; these extend to those in his community or city.  This has little to do with natural rights or a social contract:

Indeed, we must realize that for Althusius, “though the particular community may seem a matter of free choice, living together is a natural process following its own eternal principles without regard to the willful attempts of human beings, conceiving of themselves as lawgivers, absolute and subject to no laws.”

“Living together” has its own “eternal principles.”  Dwell on that for a while and consider what defending these “eternal principles” might mean for a sustainable community.  Members of the group do obligate themselves to each other, but not in a manner that we would understand as a covenant or contract:

This pact is “the fundamental organizing decision of a living group whose common life transcends this organizing act.” It is the efficient cause, the constituting power of the association, but “belongs by nature to the living groups, just as much as life belongs to the living organism.

The “common life transcends” any “organizing act”; it belongs “to the living groups.”  Dwell on these also.  This is nothing like social contract theory as it is commonly understood, nor is it a matter of individual rights, at least not in the way we understand “individual” today.  This pact is described as “the efficient cause.”  Coming from Aristotle: the efficient cause is that which brings the thing into being – what actualizes the potentiality. 

As best as I can grasp this “efficient cause” is the group and it is its own entity, and it has rights.  The community is a thing with an end or purpose.

Conclusion

While at least some libertarians would agree that a community can voluntarily form under any set of rules and conditions as the members (or “citizens”) see fit, this isn’t what Althusius is getting at.  He is driving at the community itself as its own entity with rights in its survival, with “survival” being described as something along the lines of subsidiary governance and Calvinist tradition.

At the risk of being way off base, I see something of Hoppe here.  To be clear, I fully believe that Hoppe would agree that a community is free to live under any rules that its members choose.  But Hoppe also suggests that for a community to develop and maintain something approaching libertarian governance, there are some rules and conditions that are more valuable than others – even necessary.

I have not read Hoppe to ever write that the “community” has “rights”; I am not going that far in introducing him here.  Just that I see some similarities in that both Althusius and Hoppe see the necessity of certain conditions that must be maintained at the community level for a community to survive in a healthy and peaceful manner.

Sunday, June 2, 2019

The Sailboat to Liberty


Mike Rozeff is continuing his examination of the sailboat problem and its implications for libertarian law.  I am very grateful to Rozeff, as, unbeknownst to him, he is pushing me to dive into a topic that I consider both fundamentally important (and also overwhelming).

Rozeff is now answering some of the questions raised by this sailboat dilemma.  I will review a few of his responses (as I had already addressed many of these in my initial examination) before boarding this sailboat to liberty.

It will be recalled that RB (Rothbard-Block) have concluded that throwing the girl off of the sailboat into shark infested waters was their right, given that the boat is their property.  Within the strictest application of the non-aggression principle, Rozeff asks, and then answers, the questions:

Have RB interpreted libertarian law correctly? 

Yes, I think so.

There was a time I would have said no – and in fact did say no in regards to the example of shooting a child as punishment for stealing an apple.  My strong reaction to this sent me on a path – one of a few paths that have converged to bring me to the point of recognizing that there is a difference between purifying libertarian law (as deducible from private property rights) and finding liberty.  Liberty will not be found at the end of the road of purifying libertarian law.

I do believe that there is a line when punishment – and even defense – gets crossed and one enters into initiating aggression.  What informs this line?  It will not be found in the non-aggression principle.  Proportionality is not deducible from “don’t hit me first; don’t take my stuff.”

Why must there be an end to the trespass, if there is one? Why do RB’s absolute rights prevail?

There does not have to be an end to the trespass. That’s up to the sailors. Their rights to their property prevail in the theory, but not necessarily in the ethical reality in which we live. That ethical context isn’t in libertarian law.

If all we are after is liberty as offered in the theory, why is an ethical context necessary at all?  We only need an ethical context if we believe that the non-aggression principle is not sufficient to find and sustain maximal liberty for the maximum numbers in society. 

If we believe the NAP is sufficient, there is nothing for Rozeff to question; if we believe the NAP is not sufficient, then the questions must be asked: On what do we base this ethical context?  Where will we find it?  By process of elimination, the NAP either does or does not offer or otherwise create the proper ethical context sufficient to find and sustain maximal liberty for the maximum numbers in society.

Rozeff is looking to the market to provide the ethical context:

If it is moral to save the girl (Rothbard acknowledges that he’s concerned with legal rights not the morality of abortion), is it a failing of libertarian law not to handle it in a case as startling as this one?

Yes, it’s a failing. However, it’s by no means fatal because we cannot know what law will emerge through market processes, given a chance to. I think what might happen in a private law society is that insurers would incorporate ethical provisions into their agreements.

Insert ethical provisions based on what ethics? 

Will insurance companies be the entities to provide ethical context?  Why do they not do so today?  Could it be because they find that the market will not pay for these?   Or do we look around us and conclude: “yes, in the marketplace created by the society around me, I am comfortable we will find proper ethical context”?

But why do we even need an ethical context?  The market – based on private property – will be, apparently, sufficient.  Rozeff expands on this further, in another post exploring this question:

In a free market, insurers of people’s lives may offer rewards for those who rescue people in perilous situations. This saves them from having to pay death benefits. All sorts of innovations become possible that simultaneously reward ethical behavior and increase safety.

I am no expert on insurance regulations, and each state has its own regulators; however, I do not know of a reason why an insurance company is precluded – by law or regulation – from providing such a reward today.  Heck, any individual is free to make public such a reward if he chooses: “Save me from dying, and I will pay you $1000.”  After all, the reward is only meaningful if would-be rescuers know about it.  What could possibly go wrong?

I can think of market reasons why it is not provided: how easy it would be to create such “life-saving” scenarios and then collect from the insurance company.  Sure, there will be investigations and the like, yet I think it cannot be denied that this false-scenario reality is a friction to the market providing just such rewards.

Did RB end the life indirectly or directly? Is gentle eviction from the boat a fiction? Does gentle eviction get RB off the hook?

If her life is ended, it’s directly. Gentle eviction is a fiction in this case. If there is justice beyond property ownership, RB are not off the hook. Such justice would have to consist of rules beyond property ownership.

But if we are to believe that insurance companies might provide a means – via property ownership rules – to establish such justice, why do we need rules beyond property ownership?

Saturday, June 1, 2019

Thin Libertarianism Applied


Mike Rozeff has, on and off, continued an examination of abortion and Walter Block’s evictionism.  His most recent post examines the reasonably analogous example of a shipwreck survivor.  Rozeff links to a Block blog post, in which Block receives via an emailer the following scenario:

“A ten-year-old girl survives a shipwreck and is floating around in the ocean surrounded by sharks. A Libertarian comes along in a sailboat. The ten-year-old climbs onto the sailboat to save herself and the Libertarian picks her up and throws her back into the water, shouting, ‘How dare you trespass on my boat!’ She drowns.”

Rozeff considers this “almost exactly the same as the abortion case,” while recognizing that in the case of abortion the owner of the “sailboat” (so to speak) voluntarily allowed the passenger on board.  Rozeff cites Block on abortion / evicitionism (and an example that demonstrates that despite the fine line Block attempts to draw between these two terms, there really is no distinction):

However, if the ‘gentlest manner possible’ implies the death of this very young human being, then so be it: the mother still has that right.” [Emphasis added [by Rozeff].]

To which Rozeff concludes:

If gently sliding the girl back into the ocean implies her death, then “so be it”. The libertarian sailors have that right.

He then offers that Rothbard says pretty much the same as Block.

Rozeff paraphrases the steps implied in this lifeboat / trespass / shark example and then offers: “I suggest that each step here be examined closely to find weak spots in the theory.”  I suggest that these aren’t weak spots in the theory; these demonstrate the weakness of expecting more from the theory than it is intended to deliver.

Rozeff then follows-up with some questions.  I will offer – and address – a few of these, and conclude with some summarizing thoughts (note: “RB” in the below means “Rothbard-Block”):

Does absolute ownership in this case imply RB may cause a life to end?  …Have RB interpreted libertarian law correctly?

We certainly have seen this argued from at least one other libertarian, and in the thinnest of libertarianism I cannot find a basis with which to argue.  Other than me, no one publicly argued against just such a position by a prominent libertarian a few years ago, so this can be considered as evidence in support of RB.

What happened to Rothbard’s theory of proportionality in punishment? Why does it or a variation or extension of it not apply?

It could apply (and I would argue, it would damn both the sailboat owners and the pregnant woman), but the concept of “proportionality” cannot be clarified via a thin application of the non-aggression principle.  It is a question that can only be answered by custom and tradition.  The NAP offers: “Don’t hit me first; don’t take my stuff.”  How does one find proportionality in this?

Is the ten-year-old guilty or innocent? Do the circumstances in some way mean that she’s not trespassing? Why are her rights inferior?

Under the thinnest of thin libertarianism, she is guilty of trespass.  What rights does she have?  She is trespassing.  There is nothing in the NAP to suggest an appropriate manner by which the property owners can take action.  The actions is in the hands of the boat owner.

Why must there be an end to the trespass, if there is one? Why do RB’s absolute rights prevail?

On what basis, from the thinnest of thin libertarianism, would RB’s rights not prevail?  It is their property.

Conclusion

If it is moral to save the girl (Rothbard acknowledges that he’s concerned with legal rights not the morality of abortion), is it a failing of libertarian law not to handle it in a case as startling as this one?

Now we get to the meat of it.  It is not a failing of libertarian law, but it is a failing of law intended to deliver liberty.

Are we after purifying the application of libertarian theory or are we after liberty?  Because if the only acceptable manner by which societal relations are governed is thin libertarianism, we will not arrive at liberty.

In other words, this is a failure of those who believe thin libertarian law will lead to a free society.  It will not.  Just wait until the father of the child gets word of the incident.  See how long a society will stay peaceful – and, therefore, in liberty – when this is how neighbors treat neighbors.

Libertarianism is damaged by those who use it as the alpha and omega of realizing a free society.  I value and respect the NAP far too much to damn it in such a manner; I don’t expect more from the NAP than it is capable of delivering; I choose not to make of the NAP a laughingstock.

The non-aggression principle can speak to when physical punishment is or isn’t appropriate; it cannot speak to the morals necessary to establish and maintain a free society; it cannot speak to the issue of proportionality, whether in defense or punishment – and commonly recognized proportionality (in the eyes of the community) is a necessary factor in maintaining peace and, therefore, liberty. 

We would be well served to stop expecting too much from the NAP.  Doing so only degrades the principle.