Philosophy: from Greek philosophia "love of knowledge,
pursuit of wisdom; systematic investigation," from philo- "loving" + sophia
"knowledge, wisdom," from sophis
"wise, learned;"
The
Last Superstition: A Refutation of the New Atheism, by Edward Feser
…for most of the history of
philosophy and science, there was no rigid distinction between these
disciplines; “philosophy” was just that general “love of wisdom”…
Philosophers were after an understanding of the world,
whether this involved physics, metaphysics, biology, ethics, or any other
branch of science – which explains much about why we brand the most formally educated
in almost any discipline a “Doctor of Philosophy.”
This very broad view of the meaning of philosophy was true
for much of western history; it is only recently where science is somehow
considered a breed apart and the final arbiter – one might say only since the
Enlightenment.
Feser provides an overview of the philosophy of Plato and
Aristotle; in this post I will not get through all of this – much too
heavy. It will take a second post.
Plato
Feser describes Plato’s theory of forms, a complete account
of the relationships between the material and immaterial worlds. His “form” was the essence of a thing. For example, although a triangle can come in
many shapes, colors, angles, widths of the lines, etc., one could know the form
– the “triangleness” of a triangle: three sides, angles add to 180 degrees, etc. This idea of “form” is true for all things.
Further, the form exists independent of anyone knowing
it. It is there to be discovered, not
invented; it was there before our birth and will be there after our death. No one invented the idea that a triangle had
three sides, 180 degrees, etc. It just
is.
One can consider the form of the thing to be the
archetype. This “real” triangle need not
have a location in time and space; hence, if correct, Plato’s theory “proves”
that there is more to reality than time and space.
The ultimate form is the Form of the Good; to know any form,
one must know the Form of the Good. Does
Plato see this form as God? Some argue
that he does, but it only becomes apparent through his followers in later
centuries.
The word “good” is important. Feser emphasizes – he says “good” instead of
“moral values”; the term “values” implies something dependent on the person
doing the valuing – and, as we know, value is subjective, based on each
individual’s own scale. If the “good” is
as Plato describes, it is not dependent on any person’s “value.” It just is; it is not subjective:
…the good for a thing, including
for a human being, is entirely objective, it is determined by its essence or
Form and has nothing necessarily to do with what we happen contingently to
“value” or desire.
As these forms exist outside of and are not contingent on
the material world, there must be an eternal source for these forms and morality
is to be found in this source. This
Feser describes as “realism.”
Feser offers that it is very hard avoid something like
Plato’s theory: one cannot make sense of mathematics, language, science, and
even the structure of the world without this idea. He offers three sorts of things as examples
to demonstrate this point: universals, numbers, and propositions. These all exist outside of the human mind and
would exist even if there were no human minds.
The debate between the new atheists and their critics hinges
on the idea of universalism – the universal triangle, the universal redness,
the universal humanness. Plato’s realism
is abandoned by these atheists for either nominalism
– a denial that universals are real, or conceptualism
– the universals are real but they exist only in the mind.
Returning to the idea that what is good for a thing is
determined by its form: when applied to a human, this idea leads to certain
conclusions about a man, a woman and a child. A question remains: what is “good” for a
human? Define “good.” TBD.
Aristotle
Feser doesn’t give Plato a slam-dunk win; he offers
Aristotle to clean things up a bit. To
get a couple of things out of the way: first, some consider Aristotle kind and
generous, others a vain SOB; he “compared homosexuality to eating dirt” (Plato
also offered that this practice was contrary to nature); he lacked Plato’s
literary flair, although he was more down to earth.
Overall, then, Aristotle just isn’t
as “sexy” as Plato. His only advantage is being right.
Like Plato, Aristotle
is a realist within the context discussed above; however he thinks it an error
to consider that objects occupy a third realm – outside of the material or the
intellect. The triangleness only exists
in the triangle that it occupies; considered as abstractions, these only exist
in the mind.
What this means can only be understood in the context of
Aristotle’s metaphysics: “his description of the basic principles and
categories governing all reality, knowledge of which must inform any sound
scientific, ethical, political, or ideological inquiry.”
Feser warns the reader: while understanding Aristotle is
vitally important, get ready for some dry stuff! Feser describes Aristotle’s version of
realism as “the most powerful and systematic realist metaphysics ever
developed”; however, it took Aristotle’s medieval followers to complete the
development of his thought.
How
significant is Aristotle? Well, I
wouldn’t want to exaggerate, so let me put it this way: Abandoning Aristotlianism, as the founders of modern philosophy did,
was the single greatest mistake ever made in the entire history of Western
thought.
Mmmm…emphasis in original.
I think Feser really wants us to pay attention.
This abandonment has contributed to the civilizational
crisis that has plagued the west for several centuries – and has accelerated in
the last century or so. Feser offers
that there were other, non-intellectual, contributing factors – and some of
these were more important. As this is an examination of philosophy, Feser is
thus far staying in his lane:
It is implicated in the
disintegration of confidence in the rational justifiability of morality and religious
belief; …in the modern world’s corrosive skepticism about the legitimacy of any
authority, and the radical individualism and collectivism that have followed in
its wake…
Feser points to the depersonalization of man that has
followed the abandonment of Aristotle: unparalleled mass-murder; abortion’s
slaughter of countless millions; euthanasia; same-sex marriage and the sexual
revolution generally.
This list of depersonalizations is interesting: he points to
outcomes some of which an individualist could support and some that would make
an individualist shriek in horror; yet both come from the same mother of
abandoning Aristotle. Depersonalizing by
ignoring the human form has consequences, it seems.
It was the logical development of Aristotle’s ideas – as
developed by his medieval followers – that offered the powerful and systematic
intellectual foundation for Western religion and morality. The unraveling of these ideas – despite the
wishes of the new atheists – will undermine any rational and moral standards
that these atheists attempt to claim. I
would say that we already have the proof.
I will develop Feser’s views on Aristotle’s ideas in the
next post.
Really excellent start to your series, thank you.
ReplyDeleteI have read Plato a bit but I have never read Aristotle, so I am glad you will expanding on his teaching.
ReplyDeleteAny discussion of Plato and Aristotle takes me back to Francis Schaeffer who was a Christian philosopher. He wrote books tracing the history of philosophy and how those ideas showed up in Western culture. You could tell he very much liked the classical philosophers, but the villian to his story was Hegel. He claims Hegel was instrumental in transforming philosophy from an objective search for truth to the more subjective activity it is today. I wouldn't be surprised if 'nominalism' and 'conceptualism' were the fruit of some of Hegel's ideas.
I would like to propose that the biggest non-intellectual factor that lead to the the rejection of objective realism is World War 1. The depersonalization was partly responsible for the war as well. People were to be considered raw materials whether in a factory production or war destruction.
After World War 1 (and 2), there was a huge amount of disillusion with Modernity, which was based on objectivism. Hegel was before all this but I think his ideas didn't become as widely accepted until the Post Modernists built upon his ideas. Kind of like Medieval philosophers with Aristotle.
Long-time reader here and occasional commenter. I've read Feser's book at least twice, trying to absorb it all. The book is obviously not a systematic treatment of metaphysical realism, and it's not meant to be, but nevertheless it is extremely dense (in the good way). These ideas are so foundational, it's important to get them right.
ReplyDeleteI know you haven't gotten to this part yet, but I'm fascinated by some of the early enlightenment philosophers, many of whom at least claimed to be Christian, who nevertheless assisted in the dismantling of Aristotelian/Thomist thought. We've been so inculcated in the notion that the enlightenment was a great and wonderful thing, it's disorienting to have someone come along and claim it's a major source of the destruction of Western civilization.
Looking forward to your further analysis of this excellent book.
I have been slowly coming to this realization about the Enlightenment - I continue to try to put it into words. Yes, I am looking forward to Feser's treatment.
Delete