…[Thomas Aquinas] once came upon “a
holy nun who used to be levitated in ecstasy.”
His reaction was to comment on how large her feet were. “This made her come out of her ecstasy in
indignation at his rudeness, whereupon he gently advised her to seek greater
humility.”
The
Last Superstition: A Refutation of the New Atheism, by Edward Feser
Feser moves from Aristotle to Aquinas. Much of this chapter is devoted to Feser’s
examination of Aquinas’ proof of God’s existence, using and developing
Aristotle’s metaphysical logic. Further,
Feser examines the feeble responses of today’s New Atheists – the group who
claim that morality can be found without God, and in fact can only be found without God.
Why is this important to me at this blog? It isn’t to
prove the existence of God. It leads
right back to the idea of the necessity of a foundation – and a specific
foundation – if we are to move toward liberty.
To greatly summarize: Christian ethics are a required foundation for
liberty as we have come to know it in the west; without this foundation, we
have no chance for liberty.
New Atheists claim that these ethics can be had without God
– and without God, our liberty will increase.
Many libertarians also believe the same – in fact, some will say that
religion must be crushed for liberty to thrive.
Of course, I believe they are wrong, therefore – despite having the
evidence of the last century or two on my side – it seems worthwhile to explore
the reason as to why.
Feser begins by pointing out the paucity – if not complete
absence – of New Atheist arguments contra Aquinas. He really is funny when he does this – his
ability to abuse with words is fabulous.
One wonders how [Aquinas] would
have reacted to the mental and moral midgets now being marketed as “New
Atheists” who peddle stale “refutations” of theism that were themselves refuted
long before Aquinas came on the scene.
What do these New Atheists do with Aquinas? Dawkins – a biologist, not a student of
philosophy – “is the only “New Atheist” to offer anything even remotely like an
attempt to answer [Aquinas], feeble as it is.”
Sam Harris – who at least has an undergraduate degree in philosophy –
finds room to mention Feser in his book End
of Faith, yet says nothing of Aquinas and very little about the classical
arguments for God’s existence.
Daniel Dennett – “a long-established “big name” academic
philosopher” – in his 448-page book devoted to “breaking the spell” of
religion, devotes three pages to addressing the classical philosophical
arguments for God’s existence. Even
Dennett’s peers found his work lacking “philosophical depth”; Michael Ruse
offered by email to Dennett: “I thought your new book is really bad and not
worthy of you…”
Why Aquinas? He has
written perhaps eight million words examining God. Feser describes him as a towering intellect
with a single-minded devotion to God. When his brothers held him captive to
prevent his joining the Dominicans, Aquinas memorized the entire Bible and the
four books of the Sentences of Peter Lombard.
The
Four Books of Sentences (Libri
Quattuor Sententiarum) is a book of theology written by Peter Lombard in
the 12th century. It is a systematic compilation of theology, written around
1150; it derives its name from the sententiae
or authoritative statements on biblical passages that it gathered together.
A commentary on the Sentences was required of every master
of theology, and was part of the examination system. At the end of lectures on
Lombard's work, a student could apply for bachelor status within the theology
faculty.
Puny thinker Aquinas was not.
The classical argument for God’s existence is attacked by
these New Atheists as if a scientific hypothesis; instead, Aquinas is making an
argument based on the reasoning evidenced in geometry or mathematics: for
example, the Pythagorean Theorem can be reasoned through once one understands
triangularity, etc.
Geometry doesn’t work that
way. It doesn’t involve the formulation
and testing of hypotheses, after the fashion of empirical science. This hardly makes it less rational than
empirical science; it just shows that the sort of argumentation used in
empirical science is not the only kind of rational argumentation that there is.
I will not attempt to present Aquinas’s arguments here; I
will offer that these are built on the metaphysical arguments made by
Aristotle: we observe things that exist, these undergo change, and exhibit
final causes; therefore “there necessarily must be a God who maintains them in
existence at every instance.”
Metaphysical arguments cannot be dismissed as “not
scientific”; in fact, scientific arguments are built on metaphysical
assumptions: there is a physical world existing independent of our minds, there
are objective laws of logic and mathematics that apply to this objective
world. To dismiss metaphysical arguments
is to dismiss science.
As E.A. Burtt offers: “But inasmuch as the positivist mind
has failed to school itself in careful metaphysical thinking, its ventures at
such points will be apt to appear pitiful, inadequate, or even fantastic.”
In my
previous post on Feser’s work, RMB asked: “Wonder how Aristotle defended
the existence of the 4 causes. Or was it simply that he asserted and defended
the distinction of actuality and potentiality?”
To which I replied, basically…I have no idea. But, maybe, some hints of it can be found
here – in this understanding of metaphysics: premises that are obviously known
from our sensory experience.
Conclusion
As mentioned, I will not present Feser’s review of Aquinas’s
arguments for the existence of God – albeit I have marked up this section in my
copy of this book perhaps more extensively than any other pages I have read
anywhere. I will just offer:
I realize, of course, that many
will reply that there is still a fatal flaw in Aquinas’s argument insofar as
final causes don’t exist. …But they are wrong to say it. The reality of formal and final causes is
rationally unavoidable, as we will see by the end of this book.
All I can say: if final causes don’t exist, I have no idea
the point of life; if final causes don’t exist, we can all quit this
libertarianism nonsense.
Epilogue
I am going out on a limb here, but I believe that it is
through Kant that this idea of turning metaphysics into a science gained
traction. Reason must be limited to what
we “know”: the physical objects of our experience.
Turning metaphysics into a science makes it something man
can manipulate. And dominate. Like making a triangle something other than a
triangle; this could be “reasonable,” depending on who was doing the reasoning.
Aristotle finds cause in the essence of things; Kant finds
cause in the physical thing – there is no essence. Like there is no such thing as a triangle
unless there is a physical triangle. Per
Kant, it would be unreasonable to assume otherwise.
Really glad Feser/you touched on Aquinas and agree that there's never been a good argument against his "Five ways" proof.
ReplyDeleteIt's logically sound even if the conclusion doesn't lead one to believe in a Christian "god", but the existence of a god. Dawkin's attempt to discredit Aquinas's logic was a big fail and I'm not aware of any other serious attempt to discredit it.
I was also not aware of "Sentences", when I get back to reading more seriously it'll be on my list- thank you.
Aquinas: THE Theologian
ReplyDeleteDoesn't the fact that you can picture a triangle in your mind prove Kant wrong? Even if thoughts are just the result of bio-electro-chemistry in your brain, the bio-electro-chemical movements/reactions are not in themselves triangles. Therefore the picture in your mind is distinct from the tangible things going on in your brain.
ReplyDeleteMaybe I am too simple in my thinking, but it seems rather straight forward.
BM,
ReplyDeletePaul Vanderklay is a Calvinist pastor in California who provides philosophical commentary on Jordan Peterson. His recent video lays credance to your suggestion that "it is through Kant that this idea of turning metaphysics into a science gained traction".
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=V1EFRCHbuag