Nuclear
Deterrence, Morality and Realism, by John Finnis, Joseph M. Boyle, Jr., and
Germain Grisez
Many say that a weapon cannot, in and of itself, be judged
morally. The weapon is merely an object,
incapable of action without human intervention.
The morality is in the use – therefore what is to be judged is the
purpose of the deployment. In other
words, the weapon cannot be judged, however the use to which it is deployed
can.
For a typical firearm, knife, or bow and arrow, I find this
reasonable. However, what of a weapon
that cannot be so specifically aimed?
Whereas a firearm can be deployed in a manner such that it harms only the
intended target, something like a nuclear bomb cannot – it kills innocent as
well as guilty, indiscriminately. In
other words, weapons of mass destruction, by their very design – when used as
directed – will kill many besides the targets engaged in combat.
On this I am greatly influenced by Rothbard and his
view:
This is
why the old cliché no longer holds that it is not the arms but the will to use
them that is significant in judging matters of war and peace. For it is
precisely the characteristic of modern weapons that they cannot be used
selectively, cannot be used in a libertarian manner.
While some will agree with the above sentiment, there is
even a further step to explore: is it appropriate to have such weapons for use
as a deterrent? In other words, while it
is immoral to deploy such weapons (as these will kill combatants and
non-combatants alike), is it proper to utilize such weapons as deterrent – as useful
in stopping an attack before it starts due to the horrendous threat posed by
the potential retaliation?
Rothbard comments on this as well:
Therefore, their very existence
must be condemned, and nuclear disarmament becomes a good to be pursued for its
own sake. And if we will indeed use our strategic intelligence, we will see
that such disarmament is not only a good, but the highest political good that
we can pursue in the modern world. For just as murder is a more heinous crime
against another man than larceny, so mass murder – indeed murder so widespread
as to threaten human civilization and human survival itself – is the worst
crime that any man could possibly commit. And that crime is now imminent. And
the forestalling of massive annihilation is far more important, in truth, than
the demunicipalization of garbage disposal, as worthwhile as that may be. Or
are libertarians going to wax properly indignant about price control or the
income tax, and yet shrug their shoulders at or even positively advocate the
ultimate crime of mass murder?
Under libertarian thinking and common morality, Rothbard
finds no reason for the existence of such weapons –presumably include for the
purpose of deterrence. (As is often the
case, I am certain I have not read everything that Rothbard has written on this
subject.) It is the issue of deterrence that
I would like to explore, and for this reason I explore the above-mentioned
book.
I had originally intended to write several posts on this
subject, as I have with other books. I
initially believed that the material to be covered would require such a
detailed commentary.
I was wrong – the material covered is so thorough, so
detailed, and so complete; I can only do it justice by outlining the topics
covered, highlighting a few passages, and offering some relatively superficial
commentary. The authors have done a
remarkable job, and for me to try to capture the work in a meaningful way is impossible. If you want more detail, I can only suggest that
you read the book! Every angle is
covered by the authors.
The book was written during the Cold War – the Wall was
still a reality. The references are in
this context of the Cold War and the Soviet Union; however the issues are still
relevant as the weapons are still with us.
I make no attempt to clean up the Cold War references; my purpose is not
to examine these weapons only in the context of a particular time. Even today, the weapons exist, and pose the
same threat as they did during the Cold War.
It seems to me the issues are the same as always.
The authors have background in law, philosophy and ethics
respectively. The book brings together
these disciplines when addressing the issues.
References are to chapter.section from the book.
The authors consider the entire issue from the point of view
of the West, and look at the root – what, exactly, is it that the West is
intending to protect? They operate with
a worldview that suggests it is right for political leaders to look after the
security of the subject population. What
is being protected and defended is a Western way of life different than that in
the totalitarian Soviet Union.
This way of life has at its foundation certain
Judeo-Christian principles. By
implication, if the West does not live by these principles, the authors suggest
that there is little reason to protect the population from an aggressor that
also does not live by those same principles. In other words, from the point of
view of the people, one ruler not ruling with common morality is not much different
than the next.
What is deterrence?
One acts to deter when one
threatens to do something which another wants one not to do, so the other will
not do something one wants to prevent. (I.1)
The authors explore the language of deterrence used by
political leaders of the west during the Cold War. The language spoken was the
language of city-swapping – you destroy some of our cities, we will destroy an
equal number of yours. The intent was to
make the losses severe enough that there would be no net gain from any such nuclear
attack. Further, in the event that all
else failed and all was lost, the possibility of a final retribution – an
unleashing of a total retaliatory strike – was left open. Mutually Assured Destruction.
The authors provide many quotes and examples of this political
posture. They quote several leaders from
France, Britain, and the United States all supportive of the possibility of
city-swapping. City-swapping, of course,
means death and destruction brought upon the civilian population. In the case of the United States, for several
years after Hiroshima and Nagasaki, no statements were even necessary – actions
spoke louder than words on the willingness to use nuclear weapons to kill
non-combatants.
The authors go on to describe the destructive capability of
the weapons on both sides – weapons hundreds of times more powerful than those
deployed against Japan. Of such weapons,
there are thousands on each side, all aimed against the other. If launched, as intended under the thinking
of the time, it would be certain that the casualties would include countless
tens of millions of non-combatants.
The authors next look at the duty to deter.
The vast deterrent system is
maintained by governments and citizens who regard it as a practical
necessity. And there are good reasons
for judging that deterrence is necessary to maintain peace and protect the
independence of the Western democracies.
…we consider in turn what the goals
of the deterrent actually are, whether they are morally legitimate, whether the
values the deterrent protects are threatened, and why nuclear deterrence is
probably the only practical way of meeting the threat. (III.1)
The authors clarify that even though such deterrence might
be a practically necessary means to a legitimate goal, they leave for later the
examination of the legitimacy of the means.
In this chapter, the authors consider that the means is necessary:
…we conclude that no non-nuclear
defence could adequately replace nuclear deterrence if the Western nations
renounce it unilaterally. (III.5)
I am not convinced that there is no other means by which
deterrence can be adequately achieved. There
is evidence to at least question this: in support of the authors’ view, North
Korea (with a nuclear capability), despite being on the radar as part of the
evil axis, has not been invaded, while other so-called rogue nations such as
Libya, Iraq, and others without the capability have been overrun. Conversely, Pakistan – a nuclear nation – is today
a victim of undeclared war. Their
nuclear weapons have not deterred this.
Switzerland, and dozens of other nations not armed in this way, at the
same time appear to be reasonably safe from harm.
In any case, even accepting the authors’ position that there
is a practical benefit to deterrence that cannot be achieved any other way,
does this justify the making of such threats?
We hold, therefore, that at
present, and for the foreseeable future, the West’s moral responsibility to
preserve its independence against Soviet power almost certainly cannot be
fulfilled without the deterrent. It does
not follow, however, that the deterrent is morally justified.
For even if one has a serious moral
responsibility, one can be morally barred from using the only available means
to fulfill it…. If one finds oneself in circumstances such that there is no
moral way to discharge one’s positive duties, then one should not discharge
them. (III.5)
Therefore, accepting the premise that government has such a
responsibility, if the only means by which to discharge it is immoral, the
responsibility should not be discharged.
So the question is asked, is the means immoral?
Must not the deterrent be rejected
because, though a necessary means for fulfilling a grave responsibility, it
violates the stringent moral norm which excludes intentional killing of the
innocent.
According to common morality, even
a grave responsibility does not justify the means necessary to fulfill it if
choosing that means is something one must never do. Duties must be carried out by every
legitimate means, but may and must remain unfulfilled when it is impossible to fulfill
them. (IV.1)
Such morality is captured in statements such as: the end
does not justify the means; evil may not be done that good may come. Killing the innocent violates these moral
sentiments.
It is always wrong to deliberately
kill the innocent. (IV.1)
The authors conclude this based on traditional
Judeo-Christian principles. The
conclusion is certainly consistent with the non-aggression principle.
In this, I don’t mean to suggest that every individual in
the West is or must attend either a synagogue or church. Nor do I suggest that those of a faith
outside of these two (or of no faith, if such is possible) have no place in
Western society. However, there are
principles that undergird any society.
Principles in the West can be traced back to a Biblical understanding of
morals. If these principles aren’t respected in the means of defense, then what
is the point? Certainly this doesn’t hinge
on defending the right to vote!
The authors demonstrate that by applying this moral
standard, at least two components of the deterrent must be excluded: that of
city-swapping, and that of the final retaliation – mutually assured
destruction.
The authors begin by examining intent – the intent of the
individuals behind the threat and subsequent act.
What matters is the relationship
between the moral agent’s will and the death brought about, and that
relationship is specified by the agent’s intention. (IV.2)
The authors conclude that the death of innocent persons (or
non-combatants) is precisely what is intended by those who make the threat – by
innocent, those not involved in the combat and war-making business (including logistics
support, manufacturing of arms, etc.).
…whoever chooses to make the
deterrent threat intends, conditionally but really, what is threatened. If what is threatened includes the killing of
innocent persons, the threat includes an intention prohibited by common
morality. (IV.3)
…it is clear that many (at least)
of the deaths intended in the threats of city
swapping and final retaliation are not intended as
the killing of combatants, and are thus intended as the
killing of innocents…. Massive destruction of people including non-combatants
is part of what Western leaders desire the Soviet leadership to fear and take
steps to make it fear. (IV.5, emphasis in text)
As to final retaliation, the authors note that this is an
option only deployed when the war is already lost. To this, the authors suggest there are no
longer combatants – the war is over. In
other words, all killed are non-combatants because there is no more cause for
war-making.
The authors further examine other possibilities, for example:
1) that the door remains open for the actors to change their minds, or 2) it is
all a bluff. The authors conclude that
neither is realistic – too many people are involved.
In the case of actors changing their mind: even if the small
handful of individuals who have the authority to unleash such weapons know in
the back of their mind that they can change course, not all actors in the chain
do. There is a pluralism of command,
necessary to deter a decapitating strike.
What of the lone submarine commander, as one such example?
In the case of this being a bluff – it isn’t a bluff to
everyone. For many on the sending end
and for all on the potential receiving end, the threat is real. Therefore, they will act as if it is real,
and in a highly volatile situation one of these actors outside of those who are
bluffing might choose to act (or react) as he was trained to do.
Given the callous disregard for life shown by those states
with the preponderance of nuclear weapons, on what rational basis could one
conclude that the mass killing of non-combatants is a bluff?
The proposal embodied in the
deterrent policy is not some secret known only to a few well-informed
officials. The content of the proposal
is evident. For it is a public proposal,
understood and taken seriously by citizens just as it is by adversaries….
Reflections on the content of this public proposal, and on the social act which
defines it, shows that readiness to inflict unacceptable losses necessarily
involves the conditional intent to kill the innocent. (V.7)
The authors go on to examine if the nuclear deterrent must
threaten innocents – in other words, can the deterrent exist without
threatening innocents. They look at this
through the possibility of “war-winning” and alternatively of “victory
denying.” The authors believe that inherent
in the deterrent is a threat to innocent individuals:
…the route to a morally legitimate
deterrent consisting in such a capability is barred by insurmountable obstacles
– technological, strategic, political, and moral. (VI.4)
Some suggest that any action taken (including a nuclear deterrent)
in legitimate self-defense must be morally acceptable – even if the action is
immoral. In reply, the authors offer a
statement that is clearly consistent with the non-aggression principle:
…the use of deadly military force
against those not involved in the unjust use of force cannot be justified,
since the use of deadly force is justified only to counter force unjustly used.
(VII.3)
Having reviewed arguments based on morality, the authors
turn to arguments based on consequences – arguments both for and against
deterrent. Which option brings about the
greater good or lesser evil? In other
words, is the evil of nuclear deterrence necessary because the consequences of
being overrun are even worse?
This is defended by some on the basis that nothing bad has
happened yet – the strategy has not been deployed. It may be wrong to make good on the threat,
but there is no wrong in making the threat.
Of course, the authors have addressed this issue earlier in the book – that
the leadership might have a change of mind at the last minute, or know that
they are operating under a bluff.
Neither is likely possible.
Others offer that the probability of deploying the deterrent
option is so minimal that to consider the moral question is almost
irrelevant. The authors offer analysis
that suggests the probability is not as minimal as one might like; in any case
there are known events in the past that have come dangerously close to putting
the entire process in motion.
Add to this the facts of nuclear devastation. Many studies have been done, and the
devastation is not minimal. It is
widespread, it is uncontrollable, and it is lingering.
The authors look at the alternative: dead is better than red. This is simply not so, as it certainly cannot
be true for every individual potential casualty of a nuclear holocaust. Citing Lackey:
If I may hark back to those
charming debates of the 1950s, it has always seemed to me that red is better
than dead because the red can choose to be dead but the dead cannot choose to
be anything at all.
Alternatively, some who propose consequentialist arguments
offer that unilateral disarmament would reduce the likelihood of nuclear war,
while not increasing the likelihood of Soviet domination. Again, referring to examples cited earlier of
real-life situations today, this point is at least plausible.
For the authors, ultimately the question is a moral one –
not based on consequences:
Anyone who accepts the norms (often
called precepts) of common morality should judge the nuclear deterrent
immoral…. (X.1)
The book ends with the authors examining disarmament,
individual responsibilities, and finally a chapter entitled “Concluding
Christian Thoughts.”
To learn what the deterrent
actually is: that is the first responsibility of moralists and religious
leaders who wish to talk about the deterrent.
Not to talk in ignorance of the facts; not to substitute wishes for
facts; above all, not to pretend that it is something other than it is, or,
worse, connive with government officials to obtain fresh descriptions of the
deterrent threat, so that an unqualified moral condemnation of it can be
avoided. (XIV.6)
The deterrent consists of the threat, deployable on command,
of the destruction of life on earth.
Countless billions of people today, who – regardless of the political
tyranny under which they suffer – choose “red” (or today’s equivalent of any
less-than-free state) as opposed to “dead” are given no choice but “dead” if
the threat is made good. Future
generations will be recipients of untold misery. The reality of the deterrent cannot be
avoided. It must be faced for what it is
– after which one might continue to argue that this reality of threatening
nuclear holocaust and the risks and consequences that come with this threat is
better than that which is being deterred.
So: anyone who discerns the
immorality of the deterrent should at once repent. Having repented, responsible citizens will
try to help their nations escape from the slavery of the balance of
terror. (XIV.6)
Perhaps the language of repentance will turn some off. However, the non-aggression principle and
Christian morality dovetail nicely on this issue. The conclusion is the same using either set
of principles as the foundation, I believe: even for purposes of deterrence,
such weapons of mass destruction are inherently immoral – not in use, but in
existence.
For this, I return again to Rothbard, as previously cited:
This is
why the old cliché no longer holds that it is not the arms but the will to use
them that is significant in judging matters of war and peace. For it is
precisely the characteristic of modern weapons that they cannot be used
selectively, cannot be used in a libertarian manner.
If one equates the libertarian term
“non-aggression principle” and the authors’ use of the term “common morality”
(reasonable, given the context), these three authors come to the same
conclusion.
Thankful to have come across this since topics & articles such as this were pretty much still in vogue back in the late 70's/early 80's (and correctly so).
ReplyDeleteI find it interesting in a disheartening way that nukes (or mostly the possessors of them and their interment) are not discussed as much anymore with occasional exception. Is anyone concerned with what is being/has been done with them since the end of the Cold War and the fall of the Berlin Wall?
I am being slightly humorous with my last sentence.