Imagine the liberty in such a world. Even if weighed down by a republican or
democratic form of government, imagine if every legislator had such power. Imagine no more: there was a time and place
where this was quite true! And no, the
outcome was not chaos, but a true check on kingly abuse.
In the conclusion of the first part of his book Kern
has written a summary of the major points he has raised. I will freely make use of this summary, as he
has organized the points far better than I could.
The relationship between monarch
and subject in all Germanic communities was expressed by the idea of mutual
fealty, not by that of unilateral obedience.
Especially in the time of the early Middle Ages, there was
no concept of the king as sovereign. There
was also no concept of the people as sovereign.
The king is below the law….if the
monarch failed in these duties – and the decision of this question rested with
the conscience of every individual member of the community – then every
subject, every section of the people, and even the whole community was free to
resist him, to abandon him, and to seek out a new monarch.
Both king and people had a duty to the law; the duty was not
to each other. Kern offers an example of
King Clovis, who wished to retain a costly vase over and above his due in order
to donate it to the church. All agreed
to this except one, who ended up enforcing his objection by smashing the vase. It should be noted, the king found an
indirect manner to exact revenge; this had to wait one year, based on an
equally exaggerated instance where the king’s opponent stumbled in his duty and
obligation.
Note, neither the king nor the majority had authority to
punish this act directly. The only
recourse was to find some other failure in the opponent and use this as a
pretext for revenge. It strikes me as a
demonstration that the unyielding approach taken by the king’s opponent was not
always the best idea. More importantly,
it was left open to each individual to decide where the line should be drawn.
As time passed, the right of each individual to object
evolved into the right of the community.
But in no way did this change the fact that the king was held to be
below the law. Can you imagine if a
single congressional representative (for example Ron Paul) had the authority to
kill any proposed legislation? While not
the authority of the individual, still the idea that it takes unanimity for the
state to act is a powerful idea.
Onto this secular element in
mediaeval monarchy, the ecclesiastical theory of magistracy was grafted….the
Church is authorized to declare the judgment of God.
The introduction of the Church into the relationship between
king and people slowly began to change and somewhat diminish the authority of
the people – it would seem to the benefit of both king and bishop. The view of the church went from one of
passive obedience to a sacramental consecration.
Any steps taken to sanctify the king, make him God’s chosen,
would begin to diminish the role and manner the people had to resist the king’s
authority – at the same time, increasing the church’s power. In this, one can find the beginnings of what
would become known as the divine right of kings.
The church began to take over the role of deciding when the
king overstepped his bounds:
The ecclesiastical theory of
resistance is to be distinguished from this Germanic and feudal right of
resistance, which was based on the idea of mutual fealty.
Between the idea of the people as the check on the king and
the church as the check on the king, eventually the concept of constitutional
monarchy emerged victorious:
[Constitutional monarchy] sought,
by reconciling the extremes, to enforce the central idea of the early mediaeval
State more vigorously and more permanently than the Germanic and ecclesiastical
doctrines of divine right and of the right of resistance had succeeded in doing….It
allowed the king to accomplish the most important constitutional acts of State
only in co-operation with his subject, i.e. with popular representatives and
ministers; but it gave to such acts so strong and unchallengeable a validity,
that no right of resistance could be admitted.
The Magna Carta is often pointed to as the inspiration
behind many future constitutions. From
Wikipedia:
The 1215 charter required King John
of England to proclaim certain liberties and accept that his will was not
arbitrary, for example by explicitly accepting that no "freeman" (in
the sense of non-serf) could be punished except through the law of the land, a
right which is still in existence today.
Magna Carta was the first document
forced onto a King of England by a group of his subjects, the feudal barons, in
an attempt to limit his powers by law and protect their privileges. It was
preceded and directly influenced by the Charter of Liberties in 1100, in which
King Henry I had specified particular areas wherein his powers would be
limited.
Given my understanding based on Kern’s scholarship, I don’t believe
this document represented a step forward, but a step back. Even the Wikipedia entry makes a passing note
in this regard:
In practice, Magna Carta in the
medieval period did not generally limit the power of kings…
I commented on this recently at The Daily Bell, and reprint a
portion of my comments here:
“The Magna Carta was an early
attempt to rein in government, reduce the scope of monarchical rule.”
I don’t believe this is an accurate
statement. The Magna Carta codified the
main characteristics of what had been the practice for centuries in the Middle
Ages. I suspect it is beneficial that we
believe the Magna Carta was a milestone, or significant change in direction, as
it then minimizes the risk of looking further back – into the “dark ages” – to
find a healthier relationship between the king and the people.
There had been a long-standing
right of resistance to the monarch if he abused his position of subservience to
the law – from the earliest times of the Middle Ages (immediate post western
Rome). This right, Germanic and feudal
in origin, was secured in a constitutional method in the Magna Carta; but the document
only formalized what had been a well-known and well-respected concept: the king
as well as the people were below the law, and if the king overstepped, the
people had not just the right, but the responsibility to act. All (even the king) owed allegiance to the
law (not the king), and all had duty to it.
The constitutional form has protected the monarch from the
people much more than it has protected the people from the monarch – certainly when
compared to earlier mediaeval times. At
the same time, the constitutional form has provided virtually no protection of
limiting the actions of the monarch – even for those constitutions with some
form of natural rights embedded – for example, the Bill of Rights in the U.S.
Constitution.
It seems, instead of the pinnacle of governance and
protection of liberty, the constitutional form represents a significant step
back from the liberties afforded to even the lowliest members of early
mediaeval society.
As I mentioned in an earlier post on this subject, I do not
intend to present an idealized, romantic view of political life in mediaeval
times. Certainly, when life was very
local and individuals knew all those within the community, methods of
governance could be different than those that we live under today. What might have been effective in one
circumstance could not be so in another.
However, I will suggest that the mediaeval idea seems more
enlightened. Each individual had a
direct say in his relationship with the king and community – not just a “vote”,
but a “veto.” Certainly, there were
times when he had to defend his position through coercion; yet are not family feuds
preferable to wars between nation-states?
There are those who look for a final arbiter – a concept
that would have been alien to the mediaeval mind. Each man was the final arbiter. Many would point to the chaos that might
result if such was the case today – yet the logical conclusion of reaching for
this final arbiter is to perfect world government. After all, despite mechanisms like the United
Nations and World Court, in the end if a modern state does not wish to bow to
the wishes of an outside party, it can stand off to the point of war.
There was the law. Both
king and community owed a duty to respect and defend the law – as each
individual understood it. If anything
was to be considered the final arbiter, it was this:
To the early mediaeval mind, king and
people together, welded into a unity which theoretical analysis can scarcely
divide, formed the State. Sovereignty,
if it existed at all, resided in the law which ruled over both king and
community. But any description of the
law as sovereign is useful only because it emphasizes the contrast with later
political ideas; otherwise it is better avoided. The blunt “either-or” of later times – either
the king is unlimited or the people is sovereign – is an impossible dilemma
from the standpoint of the early Middle Ages.
But what is the law as understood to the mediaeval man? This will come in Kern’s next, and final, chapter.
No comments:
Post a Comment