I continue with my review of The
Rise and Decline of the State, by Martin Van Creveld. The introduction can be found here.
Van Creveld’s opening chapter covers what he describes as
the time before the state – pre-history to AD 1300. In this chapter, he reviews tribes – with and
without rulers, city-states, and early empires – e.g. China and Egypt. In this post I will focus on his section
regarding the city-state. As in all such
sweeping views of even a specific aspect of history, much of what is written is
a generalization – not all aspects will be found in every city-state.
…the outstanding feature of
classical city-states was that their citizens appointed certain persons among themselves to govern all of them.
…we are talking here not of rulers but of magistrates.
Unlike many of the tribal societies before, governance of
the city-state was not based on descent.
This position also did not come with the concept of “ownership”; the
appointed magistrates did not “own” all of the property or the people – they
were not necessarily the wealthiest or most powerful citizens of the city, they
did not lord over the other citizens:
On the contrary, in both Greece and
Rome “government” (arche, imperium)
was defined as a form of authority exercised by some persons over others who,
unlike family members and slaves, were their equals (homoioi) in front of the law and did not “belong” to them…
There was no distinction corresponding to our customary (and
superficial) separation of executive, legislative, and judicial branches. Instead, “[p]erhaps the most important single
institution was the popular assembly.”
Rome was perhaps unique in that it had four different
assemblies, each comprising a different section of the population; elsewhere,
one assembly was found – an assembly of all adult makes, excluding those who
were part of another household, slaves, and foreigners. In Athens, some forty meetings per year were
held:
The assembly’s main function was to
pass laws, known as nomoi in Greece
and leges in Rome; but it also
elected the magistrates and pronounced the final word on questions of war and
peace.
The assembly also possessed the right to use ostracism in
order to exile those citizens felt to be a public danger – an approach
sometimes suggested as viable by those advocating a more libertarian / anarchic
solution to certain offenses.
Next in importance to the assembly
were the various magistrates. Whereas
many might be selected by lot, the most important ones were invariably elected…
In Greece…the objective was usually to enable as many citizens as possible to
rule and be ruled in turn.
The process of selection by lot is known as sortition:
…election by lot, a method of
choosing public officials in some ancient Greek city-states. It was used
especially in the Athenian democracy, from which most information about the
practice is derived. With few exceptions, all magistrates were chosen by lot,
beginning with the archons in 487–486 bc; likewise the Boule (council) of 500
and the juries of the law courts were chosen by lot. The practice of sortition
obviated electoral races and provided for the regular turnover of
officeholders. The operations of government were thus not in the hands of
experts, but, through the system of sortition, the Athenian democracy provided
at least some practical political education for its citizens.
The rationale of sortition was the
equality of all citizens.
We could do worse than elect our politicians by lot…wait a
minute…we already do worse!
The situation of law, crime, and punishment deserves
mention. There were several courts in
which a trial could be judged. The
system was a jury system:
Thus, in Athens, the assembly
elected a pool of 6,000 potential jurors each year; to forestall bribery, the
decision as to who would serve on each court each day was made by lot with the
aid of a specially constructed machine…In this way the classical city-state
became the first, and for a very long time only, political community to take
juridical powers out of the hands of the ruler(s). No magistrate, not even the Roman consuls
whose power was greater than that of all the rest, in an ancient city-state
possessed the right to inflict capital punishment on a citizen in peacetime
unless he had first been permitted to present his case before a citizens’
court….
There was no concept of committing a crime against the
state:
In the absence of the state as a
legal persona against which offenses
could be committed, our modern distinction between civil and criminal
jurisdiction did not apply. It made no
difference whether the matter before the court involved a dispute over an
inheritance or murder; instead a line was drawn between cases which involved
only individuals and those which, like peculation, treason, impiety, and – in
Rome – insulting the greatness or majestas
of the Roman people, concerned the community as a whole. In the former cases, the only ones who could
bring suit were the injured person or, if he was no longer alive, his
relatives; the second type could be prosecuted by any citizen who wished to do
so.
There is, perhaps, some applicability in this to the
concepts of law and justice in a more libertarian / anarchic society.
There was little concept of specialized personnel, large
administrative bureaucracies, or regular armies. There was no institutional training of
personnel for positions in police work, accounting, or diplomacy. The laws themselves, at least initially, came
from oral tradition – similar to the discovery of law during the Middle Ages.
The expenditures of government were met with market duties
and proceeds from the justice system.
The most important source, however, was the so-called liturgies –
contributions made by the wealthier citizens for specific purposes: staging a
play, supplying an exercise hall, or erecting a public building. Beyond any altruistic motives, such payments
often helped to increase popularity and therefore gain sympathy from a jury
pool – as such wealthy people were certain to be dragged into court on occasion.
Voluntary payments for so-called public goods; an
interesting idea. Instead of buying off
the politicians via “campaign contributions,” they bought off the population
directly, thus circumventing the tremendously expensive middle-man.
Thus ends Van Creveld’s overview of the governance in an
ancient city-state; in addition to my being exposed to this history, it also
provides real-world examples of institutional possibilities absent a (or at
least via a greatly reduced) central, monopoly state government.
No comments:
Post a Comment